Monotheletism: A Heresy or a Form of
Words?1
Richard M. Price
‘Energies’
(operations, activities) and ‘wills’ in God the Word incarnate – should we as
‘dyenergists’ and ‘dyotheletes’ talk of two, or as ‘monenergists’ and
‘monotheletes’ talk of one? After the Council of Chalcedon (451) with its insistence
on ‘two natures’ in Christ, it was more natural to talk of two energies – since
everything that exists has ‘energy’ in the sense of having effects – and indeed
of two wills, since, as we shall see, ‘will’ was used in a loose sense that did
not distinguish it clearly from ‘energy’. Yet the terms ‘one energy’ and ‘one will’
could serve the purpose of filling out the notion of the ‘one person’ of Christ,
since the term ‘person’ was exceedingly vague in late antique usage. The
Antiochene theologians Theodore of Mopsuestia and Nestorius, in quest of a
clearer way to express Christ’s unity, were happy to talk of ‘one energy’ and ‘one
will’ in Christ, despite the Antiochene emphasis on the completeness and freedom
of Christ’s manhood. This, by the way, is a clear and important indication that
these expressions did not necessarily imply docking Christ’s humanity of energy
and will.
The
Chalcedonian theologians showed awareness of the dangers of both forms of expression:
‘two energies/wills’ could sound like a Nestorian division of Christ, while
‘one energy/will’ could read like a surrender to the one-nature (miaphysite)
Christology of the anti-Chalcedonians. In the seventh century, however, the
emperors and patriarchs of Constantinople adopted first monenergism and then
monotheletism, in the hope of winning back the miaphysites into communion with
the imperial, Chalcedonian Church. Opponents of this policy accused it of being
a revival of Apollinarianism – monotheletism being understood as a denial of
the presence in Christ of a human faculty of will. Was this accurate? Or were
the monenergists and monotheletes perfectly conventional in their understanding
of Christ’s make-up and operation, in such a way that ‘one energy’ and ‘one
will’ meant no more than the perfect and total cooperation of energies and
wills in Christ?
Two recent
books, both by Eastern Orthodox scholars, argue that monenergism and
monotheletism were indeed Apollinarian,2 but
much western scholarship has been sceptical.3
The question is hard to resolve, since we do not have enough monenergist and
monothelete writing – perhaps there never was very much – and since one’s
answer to the question will depend on whether one assumes that the great
critics of monenergism and monotheletism (such as Sophronius of Jerusalem and
Maximus the Confessor) must have known what they were talking about, or whether
on the contrary one considers it more likely that the champions of monenergism
and monotheletism were perfectly conventional in their understanding of Christ,
despite the rules they tried to impose in the matter of terminology. This paper
adopts the latter position; but I am not so sanguine as to imagine that I shall
convince the other side. I am reminded of a remark made by the nineteenth-century
English wit Sydney Smith on a visit to Edinburgh: he saw two women leaning out of
their respective windows across a narrow alley to shout at each other, and
commented, ‘Those two women will never agree: they are arguing from different premises.’
1 References,
unless otherwise stated, are to volumes in Acta Conciliorum Oecumenicorum,
Series 2, vol. 1, 2.1 or 2.2 (Berlin, 1984-92).
2 Demetrios
Bathrellos, The Byzantine Christ (Oxford, 2004), esp. ch. 2; Cyril
Hovorun, Will, Action and Freedom: Christological Controversies in the
Seventh Century (Leiden, 2008).
3 Of
this a magisterial example is M. Jugie in: Dictionnaire de Théologie
Catholique 10.2 (Paris, 1929), 2310-1.
I
Let us begin
by taking a quick look at the ‘monenergism’ promoted in the earlier part of his
reign by the emperor Heraclius (610-41). What did it amount to?
Take the
much-disputed sentence in the Tome of Pope Leo: ‘Agit enim utraque forma cum
alterius communione quod proprium est’ (‘Each form [= nature] performs what is
proper to itself in communion with the other’).4
All this does is to apply to Christology the metaphysical (or rather,
commonsense) principle that every physical entity has effects.5 But the passage that follows in the Tome on
the distinction between the divine and human operations in Christ collapses
with the statement that, while it is human to hunger or thirst, it is divine to
walk on water. But obviously only bodies can walk on water; as Maximus the Confessor
rightly stated: ‘He shows through this crossing [of the water] that the natural
energy of his own flesh is inseparable from the power of his divinity’ (PG 91,
1049B-C). Leo was to correct his apparent separation of the inseparable in Ep.
124.5: the flesh does not act without the Word nor the Word without the
flesh. This became a standard assertion: in the words of St Maximus: ‘He did
not do divine things divinely, since he was not only God; nor did he do human
things in a human way, since he was not mere man’ (PG 91, 593A). Pope Martin in
the Acts of 649 likewise denies two separate operations: ‘He did not perform
the divine acts divinely and the human humanly’ but ‘the divine ones humanly
and the human ones divinely’; the miracles were performed through the flesh,
and he accepted the sufferings ‘according to his omnipotent power’ (1, pp.
148-50). What is the difference between this and the one ‘theandric’
(divine-human) operation taught by the monenergists? Compare the monothelete
Macarius of Antioch at the Third Council of Constantinople (680/1): ‘We believe
that the miracles and the sufferings are of the same [person] and that, in a
word, the whole divine and human operation proceeds from one and the same
Christ our God, for he did not perform the divine things divinely and the human
ones humanly, but after becoming man God the Word exhibits a new theandric
operation’ (2.1, p. 222, 17-21).
Or did the
monenergists deprive the human nature of its proper operation by treating it as
an utterly passive instrument manipulated at every stage, like a lever, by the
divine operation? This may seem implied by the following statement from the
monothelete Ecthesis: ‘At no time did his rationally ensouled flesh
perform its natural movement separately and as a result of its own impulse
contrary to the will of God the Word united to it hypostatically, but whenever
and of whatever kind and to whatever extent God the Word wished’ (1, p. 160,
26-9). But the advocates of orthodox dyenergism said exactly the same. To cite
the dyenergist champion Sophronius of Jerusalem: ‘He did not undergo them
[thirst, passion, and the rest] involuntarily or under compulsion, even if he
acted with human movements.., but did so when the same [God the Word] had
willed to suffer, do, and operate humanly.., and not when the physical and
fleshly movements wished to be physically stirred into operation’ (2.1, p.
450.10-16). Or take Anastasius of Sinai: we experience the passions
(emotions and bodily drives) out of necessity, but ‘Christ, being the God and
master and maker of nature, guided the things of nature when he wanted and as
he wanted.’6 Or Pope Martin: ‘He
allowed the entirely blameless passions to move in him according to his will’
(1, p. 360, 6-7). Or St Maximus: Christ experienced hunger and thirst and the
like differently from us, since he underwent them not out of natural necessity
but voluntarily (PG 91, 297D).7
In all, the
difference between monenergism and dyenergism seems to have been a matter of
terminology rather than of substance.
4 ACO
II 2 (Berlin, 1932),
28, 12-3.
5 See
Anastasius of Antioch at 1, p. 435, §74, 12-3, ‘It is plain that every nature
or essence has its own energy.’
6 Anastasius,
Sermo 1, VI 3.58-65 (CChr.SG 12, 111).
7 All
these passages should surely be taken to assert not that the human nature
entirely lacked spontaneity, but that it only yielded to hunger, distress and
the like when the divine will permitted it, while at all other times the divine
will kept the weakness of the flesh in check. See Gregory of Nyssa: ‘[The Word]
when he so wished gave the [human] nature the opportunity to exercise its own
operation’ (PG 44, 1237A), and Cyril of Alexandria: ‘He submitted himself to
the infirmities of mankind’ (Homily on Luke 146).
II
The Ecthesis
issued by the emperor Heraclius in 638 abandoned monenergism in favour of
‘monotheletism’. What did this mean? St Maximus accused the monotheletes of not
knowing what they believed (PG 91, 329C – 332A).
That at least
some monothelete statements were no more than a verbal variant on orthodoxy can
scarcely be denied. For example, the monothelete Themistius states that, even
though Athanasius said that at the time of the passion Christ displayed two
volitions (qelsmata), he would not acknowledge two wills (qelsseiˇ) in Christ,
but rather one that is ‘moved in part humanly and in part divinely’ (2.1, p.
506, 21-4). The use of the expression ‘one will’ to mean simply harmony of will
was a common usage. Take, for example, the following argument attributed to
Pyrrhus in the Disputation with Pyrrhus: if will pertains to nature, as
Maximus claimed, then the saints, who have one will with God, will be of the
same essence with him (PG 91, 292B). Mark how here the phrase ‘having one will
with God’ is understood (by a monothelete!) to mean much the same whether
applied to Christ or the saints. Note also the statement by Pope Honorius: ‘We
acknowledge one will of our Lord Jesus Christ, since clearly there was assumed
by the Godhead our nature, not the sin in it but the nature created before sin’
(2.2, p. 550, 16-18). This likens the ‘one will’ in Christ to Adam’s state of
grace before the Fall. This is akin to Stephen the Monothelete’s insistence at
Constantinople III that before the Fall Adam had a divine will (2.1, p. 244,
14). His meaning was manifestly not that Adam lacked a human will – for if so,
how could he have fallen? –, but that before the Fall his will was in accord
with the will of God. This is to be borne in mind when we meet monothelete
texts that assert, as in Theodore of Pharan, that Christ ‘had only one will and
that divine’ (1. p. 122, 3-4); such a statement does not necessarily deny to
Christ a human faculty of will.
Likewise at
Constantinople III Macarius of Antioch asserted that the Godhead underwent the
sufferings of the flesh (since the flesh was not separated from him) ‘with one,
sole divine will, since there was not in him another will or one resisting his
divine and powerful will’ (2.1, p. 224, 7-11). He went on to affirm: ‘I will
not affirm two natural wills or two natural operations in the case of the
fleshly dispensation of our Lord Jesus Christ, not even if I am chopped up limb
by limb and cast into the sea’ (2.1, p. 232, 11-3). But he did not mean literally
that Christ had no human operation: he affirmed at the same session that Christ
did divine things humanly as well as human things divinely (216, 26), and he
referred to Christ’s ‘divine and human operation’ (222, 18), and to ‘the suffering
of the flesh that was not separated from the Godhead’ (224, 6). So there is
surely no need to take his denial of a natural human will in Christ any more
literally. His monotheletism is akin to the familiar miaphysitism of those who
insisted on one nature in Christ, while not denying that he had assumed flesh.
And note finally a statement by the monothelete Bishop Theodosius: ‘We too
confess that both the natures and the operations are different, that is, divine
and human, and that his Godhead is endowed with will (qeletikRn) and his
manhood endowed with will, for his soul was not without a will. But we do not
say two, lest we make him strive against himself.’8
What, then,
were the monotheletes denying? It is very striking that they invariably treat
‘two wills in Christ’ as necessarily implying two opposed wills, as in
the passage just quoted. But the notion of a human will that consistently obeys
the divine will was, and is, commonplace in Christianity; it is ubiquitous in
hagiography. Why, then, did the monotheletes consistently understand the assertion
of two wills in Christ to imply a conflict of wills?
One of the
key monothelete texts is the Letter of Sergius of Constantinople to Pope
Honorius. After saying that the expression ‘one operation’ threatens the profession
of two natures in Christ, he proceeds to say that talk of ‘two operations’ likewise
shocks many, ‘for it implies the assertion of two wills opposed to each other,
with God the Word willing to accomplish the saving passion, while his manhood
resists and opposes his will, whereby two [agents] are introduced, willing
opposite things, which is impious. For it is impossible for there to exist in
one and the same subject two contrary wills at the same time and in the same
respect’ (2.2, pp. 542,12-17). The distinguished Maximus scholarF.-M. Léthel
interprets Sergius as erring through confusion of thought – confusing the
faculty of will with the object of will. If an agent simply chose one thing,
one would talk of a single volition; talk of two volitions (with respect to one
object at one and the same time) necessarily implies two contrary volitions.9 As a result, Sergius makes the error of
supposing that two wills in Christ must involve contrariety. And since
contrariety must be denied (as excluded by the hypostatic union), the
monothelete solution, according to Léthel, was to deny that Christ possessed a
human faculty of will.10
For Léthel
this is primarily a matter of logic and metaphysics. I would suggest, however,
that the stress on the contrariety of two wills arose in the first place not
from logic but from a reading of Scripture – from the references in the Gospels
to a distinct human will in Christ. ‘I will: be clean’ to the leper at Matth.
8:3, and similar passages, get us nowhere: as Léthel himself notes (p. 35), every
statement of agreement between Christ’s will and that of the Father was read as
relating to the Trinitarian unity of will, and so the accord of Christ’s human
will with that of the Godhead became invisible. It is undeniable that a distinct
human will is being referred to only when there is reference to a created will differing
from the divine will, as we find in just two or three passages. One, often
discussed in the seventh century, comes in the Fourth Gospel: ‘I came down from
heaven not to do my own will but the will of Him who sent me’ (John 6:38).
But above all there is our Lord’s prayer at Gethsemane: ‘My Father, if it is
possible, may this cup pass from me; but not as I will, but as You will’ (Matth.
26:39), of which the Lucan version is: ‘Father, if You so will, take this cup away
from me; but let not my will but Yours be done’ (Luke 22:42).
A
particularly revealing text is one to be found in the Acts of the Lateran
Council of 649 – the ‘Second Florilegium on the natural wills of Christ’ (1,
pp. 274-97). In one excerpt (§2) Ambrose proves the difference between divine
and human will by contrasting the human aversion to death to the divine will to
undergo death in the passion of Christ. In another (§15) there is attributed to
Athanasius: ‘When he says, “Father, if it is possible, may this cup pass; but
let not my will be done but yours. The spirit is eager but the flesh is weak,”
he here reveals two wills, one human, which is of the flesh, and the other
divine, which is of God. For the human will, through the weakness of the flesh,
rejects the passion, while the divine is eager for it.’11 The florilegium contains similar statements by
Chrysostom, Theophilus, Cyril, and Severian of Gabbala. To quote the last of
these (§34): ‘At the end of his life he said, “now my soul is troubled and sorrowful
unto death” – [he said “my soul” and] not “my Godhead”, for the divine is
impassible and without fear or sorrow … In this way he displays two wills, one
divine and the other human.’ In these texts it is Gethsemane itself that takes
pride of place, as the supreme instance where Christ revealed that he had a
human will by allowing it to oppose the divine will.
But did this
not involve picturing Christ as a double monster, pursuing two contrary goals
at the same time? The answer given was that the contrariety was only temporary,
since Christ tamed the human will and overcame its resistance. The florilegium
quotes from a sermon by Athanasius (§19): ‘It was necessary to change the will
of his flesh and to subject it to the divine will’, and it also quotes Cyril’s Thesaurus
on the human will being ‘taught’ by the divine will to accept the passion
(§36). But was not the idea of even a temporary rebellion of the human will
shocking to pious ears? The answer given was that aversion to dying is simply a
natural physical reaction, without moral significance. This was stated in two passages
from John Chrysostom included in the same florilegium: (§27) ‘The will of the
flesh not to die is not reprehensible, but simply in accordance with nature,’
and (§28) ‘Just as hunger and sleep are not faults, neither is desire for the
present life. Christ had a body free of sins but not separated from natural drives.’
Note that ‘will’ is here being used in a broad sense that includes any instinctive
attraction or aversion. Compare the passage from Sophronius of Jerusalem that I
quoted above: Christ experienced the passions when the Godhead wished and not
when the physical and fleshly movements wished (≠qelon) to be physically
stirred into operation’ (2.1, p. 450, 10-16). Compare the statement of
Augustine’s in the same florilegium (§9): we call all feelings of
attraction or aversion ‘volitions’ (qelsmata, ‘voluntates’ in Augustine’s
Latin).12 We find the same loose
usage in Maximus the Confessor, as where he cites Jesus’ quailing before the
passion as proof that he did indeed have a human will (PG 91, 80C). Consider
too a passage in the Disputation with Pyrrhus where he cites from Mark
the verse ‘He did not want to be recognized but was unable to remain hid’ (7:24)
and observes that this implies limited power and therefore a human volition (PG
91, 321C-D). Here mere preference or velleity is treated as an operation of the
will.13
Sergius of
Constantinople avoided a clash of wills between the Godhead and the manhood by
insisting that what we find at Gethsemane is not a contrary human volition but
a ‘will’ in the weaker sense of simply a natural movement of the flesh, a mere
reflex action, that the divine will was able to contain and deflect. Léthel (p.
45) criticizes him for reducing the refusal to a mere ‘inframoral, natural
movement of the flesh’, as the miaphysites did. But, as we have seen, the
mainstream, orthodox tradition, represented by the dyothelete florilegium used
at the Lateran Council of 649, interpreted Gethsemane in precisely the same
way; there was nothing unusual or partisan in Sergius’ understanding of
Gethsemane. The difference between him and the ‘orthodox’ is merely a terminological
one – his insistence that, despite Our Lord’s own words, he had but a single
‘will’.
Did Sergius
deny that Christ had a human will at all? In view of the tradition, in the
Church and in the very words of the gospel account of Gethsemane, that used
‘will’ to include reflex and instinctive movements, feelings such as hunger or aversion
or distress, and also mere preferences and inclinations, this option was not
open to him. Even the miaphysite champion Severus of Antioch admitted ‘two
wills’ in Christ at Gethsemane.14 Historians
of Christian doctrine have been much too ready to credit the monotheletes with
the denial to Christ of a human faculty of will. There are certainly apparent
denials of this kind, but we should be very hesitant before taking them
literally. Take, for instance, the declarations of Constantine of Apamea at Constantinople
III: he insists that Christ had but one will (qeljma), and that this one will
was identical to that of God the Father and the Holy Spirit, but then adds
unhesitatingly that Christ had a natural human will (qeljma, qeljsiˇ) meaning a
desire for such things as food, drink and sleep (2.2, pp. 696,19-698,15). What,
rather, Sergius denied is that Christ’s human ‘will’ ever operated separately
from the divine will and in opposition to it: certainly the divine will and the
instinctive impulse of the flesh differed at Gethsemane, but this was not to be
described in terms of ‘two wills’ at loggerheads with each other. Instead, as
Sergius put it, ‘The Lord’s rationally ensouled flesh never performed its physical
movement separately and of its own impulse (orms) in opposition to the will of
the Word of God hypostatically united to it, but whenever and however and to
whatever extent God the Word himself willed it’ (2.2, p. 542, 18-21).15
8 Disputatio
Bizyae cum Theodoro,
in: Scripta saeculi VII vitam Maximi Confessoris illustrantia, CChr.SG
39 (Turnhout and Leuven, 1999), 109, 387-92.
9 François-Marie
Léthel, Théologie de l’agonie du Christ (Paris, 1979), 41-4. See Pyrrhus
in St Maximus’ Disputation with Pyrrhus: ‘It is impossible for two wills
to coexist in one person without contrariety’ (PG 91, 292A). See the
monothelete statement: ‘Equality of volition by all means indicates one will,
just as equality of nature indicates one nature’ in: Sebastian Brock, Two sets
of monothelete questions to the Maximianists: Orientalia Lovaniensia
Periodica 17 (1986), 119-40, esp. 133.
10 F.-M.
Léthel, Théologie (1979), 28 and 44-5.
11 Note
that Athanasius was specially cited by Pope Martin in 649 as authoritative on
the two wills in Christ (1, 342, 21-2).
12 Consequently,
let us note, there was no real distinction between ‘energy/operation’ and
‘will’.
13 St
Maximus in polemical contexts had little choice but to employ the loose use of
‘will’ of his contemporaries, but for his own awareness of the need to make
distinctions between such terms as fusikon qeljma, bouljsiˇ, proairesiˇ and the
like see Opuscula Theologica 1 (PG 91, 9ff.).
14 See
the passages cited in Aloys Grillmeier, Christ in Christian Tradition,
2.2 (London, 1995), 167.
15 He
gives the same account verbatim in the Ecthesis when explaining what is
meant by denying two contrary wills and asserting one will in Christ (1, p.
160).
III
In all, in
the tradition and on both sides of the seventh-century debate, the role of the
human will was constantly reduced to an instinctive, knee-jerk reaction of the
flesh, which was merely a part of the natural human energy or operation. But
there was an alternative – to interpret the opposition to the divine will as real,
even culpable, but to attribute it to Christ only by appropriation, as in St
Paul’s statement: ‘He made him to be sin who knew no sin’ (2Cor. 5:21).16
In Maximus
the Confessor’s Disputation with Pyrrhus, Pyrrhus is made to refer to
‘men of Byzantium’ who attribute a human will to Christ not according to nature
but by ‘appropriation’, meaning, as the text explains, not ‘essential appropriation’,
that is, actual possession (through taking on new qualities and experiences)
but rather a mere relation, by which ‘we appropriate and cherish out of
friendship what belongs to others, without performing or suffering it ourselves’
(PG 91, 304A). In this sense Christ took on ignorance, abandonment, and even
rebellion against the divine will, not personally but in one might call sympathetic
solidarity. One extant monothelete text (the First Aporia of Deacon Theodore
of Constantinople, PG 91, 216B-C) expresses precisely this view, likening the
ascription to Christ of a human will to the ascription to him of ignorance
(which, after the condemnation of the Agnoetae in the sixth century, was never
taken literally). Since the natural object of appropriation is an experience rather
than a faculty, by ‘human will’ in these texts is probably meant yet again the
human ‘will’ at Gethsemane. This is explicit in Pope Honorius’ First Letter
to Sergius of Constantinople: ‘There was not in the Saviour “another law in
the members” or a differing or contrary will … Even if it was written: “I came
to do not my will but the will of the one who sent me”, and: “Not as I will,
but you will, Father” and the like, these are indicative not of a differing
will but of the assumed dispensation of the manhood. For they were uttered on
account of ourselves, to whom he gave an example.., so that each of us should
learn to prefer in all things not his own will but rather that of the Lord’
(2.2, p. 552, 12-19). To explain the agony in the garden by appropriation in
this sense was traditional. Take Athanasius, who talked of Christ’s speaking of
his abandonment and of his ‘supposed’ fear of death: he shied away from attributing
to Christ a personal experience of fear and God-forsakenness.17 This minimizing of Christ’s share in human
weakness was not just an Alexandrian aberration: it is also to be found in John
Chrysostom, who in one of his sermons on Matthew explains that the words ‘Not as
I will but as you will’ were uttered to teach people to follow God, even if
nature is reluctant, while the words asking for the cup to pass were uttered by
Christ to prove the reality of his manhood. Likewise he interprets ‘The spirit
is willing but the flesh is weak’ as a general statement about mankind’s need
for God’s help and not as referring to Jesus’ own experience.18
The
monothelete Deacon Theodore, in the passage cited above, claims that treating
the human will as Christ’s by appropriation is to be found in Gregory Nazianzen’s
First Theological Oration on Christ (that is, Oratio 29). This is
inaccurate, but he could have cited the following oration (30. 12), where
Gregory writes that he understood ‘If it is possible, may this cup pass from
me; but not as I will’ to refer not to any ignorance as to what was possible
nor to any conflict of will in Christ, but to the limited knowledge and
refractory will of ‘humanity in our condition’ (toO kaqˆ ™m¢ˇ).
16 See
F.-M. Léthel, Théologie (1979), 50-2.
17 See
Marcel Richard, Saint Athanase et la psychologie du Christ selon les Ariens: Mélanges
de Science Religieuse 4 (1947) 5-54, esp. 34-5.
18 John
Chrysostom, Hom. in Matth. 83 (PG 58, 746-7). See M.E. Lawrenz, The
Christology of John Chrysostom: SP 22 (1989) 148-53, esp. 150: ‘Chrysostom
does not describe full human volition as a characteristic of the human
functions of Christ … Unlike later Antiochene Christology, however,
Chrysostom’s Christology does not envision the convergence of the will of the
Son and the Father as the moral accomplishment of the humanity of the Son.’
IV
Notably
absent in the debate so far is any recognition of the role of the rational will
in Christ, of the emphasis in the Letter to the Hebrews (5:8) on his
learning obedience through what he suffered.
Was the role
of the rational will in accepting the passion appreciated by the orthodox? The
answer, broadly, is No – until Maximus the Confessor, writing in the
mid-seventh century. Consider Chrysostom, Hom. 7 on the incomprehensible,
against the Anomoeans, where he argues that ‘Not as I will but as You
will’ proves that Christ had two wills and that he truly assumed a human
nature, its reality exhibited by its fear of death. He continues: ‘At one
moment he leaves the flesh on its own and deprives it of his own operation, in
order to reveal its weakness and prove its nature, and at another moment he
hides it, so that you may learn that he was not a mere man’ (PG 48, 766). All
that manhood contributes is weakness.
Or take Cyril
of Alexandria, Thesaurus (PG 75, 397A): the flesh, terrified at the
thought of death, ‘was taught not to feel this’ as the Logos ‘taught the
manhood no longer to have its own thoughts but to seek the will of God’. This
is better than Chrysostom’s treatment. Still, the whole emphasis is on the soul’s
need of healing; there is no appreciation of its positive role, and no
suggestion of human merit. And from the time of the Nestorian controversy Cyril
reverted to the Athanasian concentration on the will of the Godhead and its condescension
in allowing the flesh to experience its natural weakness, while the soul goes
unmentioned.19
For an
example of the failure of much of the seventh-century debate to focus on the
role of Christ’s rational will, take Ps.-Irenaeus, Treatise on the Faith to
Deacon Demetrius:20 this text singles out as the monothelete error not a
neglect or denial of the role of Christ’s rational will but simply a treatment
of Christ’s sufferings (distress, fear, anguish, hunger, weariness) as unreal.
Here a distinction between orthodoxy and monotheletism is achieved only by
misrepresenting the latter, for of course the monotheletes did not deny to
Christ the blameless drives and impulses of the flesh.
What of the
great dyothelete Council of Constantinople of 680/1? We read in its definition
of the faith: ‘We proclaim two natural wills, which are not contrary (perish
the thought!), as the impious heretics have asserted, but rather [we proclaim]
his human will that follows and does not oppose or resist but is instead
subject to his divine and omnipotent will, for “it was necessary for the will
of the flesh to be moved but to be subjected to the divine will” according to
the all-wise Athanasius’ (2.2, p. 774, 22-6). I used to suppose that this meant
that Christ’s rational will followed the divine will, but it is clear from
passages I have cited above that the reference is merely to instinctive human
reactions such as aversion to death. This is made crystal clear in the edict of
the emperor Constantine IV, confirming the decrees of the council, which
describes Christ’s soul as ‘voluntarily laying hold of all the blameless
passions, like our own, whenever the Word allowed it to seek and wish its own,’
and continues:
Accordingly
it desired and longed for physical nourishment, according to reason, and was
grieved and distressed; for when the Saviour came to the passion of the cross according
to free will, he began to be distressed and afraid … He then prayed that the cup
should pass, for as man he deprecated death.., while as God he was eager for
the passion … Our father Athanasius bears witness to this in the sermon on the
Trinity and the Incarnation, when he says, ‘[The words] “Father, if is
possible, let this cup pass from me, but let not my will be done but yours”
reveal two wills, the human one, which is of the flesh, and the divine; the
human one, because of the weakness of the flesh, deprecates the passion, while
the divine will is eager for it’ (2.2, pp. 842,11-844,2).
The emperor
proceeds to cite Gregory Nazianzen, Oratio 30 on the obedience of the
human will to the divine will – this is the passage I discussed above where St
Gregory explains the resistance of the flesh as mere appropriation. In all,
Constantinople III achieved no advance over the monothelete interpretation of
Gethsemane.21
Did the
monotheletes likewise fail to appreciate a human assent to the passion in
Christ? There is an intriguing passage in the letter of the monothelete patriarch
Paul of Constantinople to Pope Theodore I (1, pp. 196-204), that offers the
following interpretation of ‘Not my will but yours be done’. This, he says,
means that Christ did not possess or exercise a will contrary to the
divine will (this closely follows Gregory Nazianzen, Oratio 30. 12). The
correct teaching, he continues, is that Christ passionlessly appropriated ‘our
human nature in its not choosing to be separated from the present life’ and
that we must not suppose ‘that the flesh of God the Word, ensouled as it was
by a mind, was averse to the passion that saved the world or differed in
mind from the Father and the Word that indwelt it’ (1, p. 202, 10-14). This
seems to hint at an acceptance of the passion by the rational soul, but it is
hesitant and undeveloped.
It is to St
Maximus that we must turn for a realization that at Gethsemane it was the human
will that, voluntarily and of its own impulse, accepted the passion. Christ’s
words ‘Not my will but Yours be done’ refer to a natural aversion to death but
constitute an acceptance of the cross by the human, rational will.22 This the monotheletes missed, but so did the
tradition that preceded them, and so did Constantinople III. This surely means
that the debate over energies and wills in the seventh century was to a large
extent an unreal one; monotheletes and most dyotheletes shared the same
traditional view (and surely a defective one) of the operation of Christ’s
manhood. What was novel in monotheletism was simply elevating the language of
‘one will’ in Christ (a traditional expression of a perfect harmony of will)
into a requirement of orthodoxy; the motive for this was doubtless to win back
the miaphysites, a motive that one can call ‘political’ or, more generously,
‘ecumenical’. The worst one can justly say of monotheletism is that it encouraged
(though it did not always involve) a reduction of the agony in the garden
to mere appropriation, and that it reinforced the failure in orthodoxy
(apart from St Maximus) to recognize the role of the rational will in Christ.
In all, it embodied what was most defective in orthodoxy, but it belonged to
the same current. It was not unorthodox.
To conclude,
the traditional picture – affirmed by the dyotheletes in the seventh century
and repeated constantly ever since – is that there was, from the time of
Chalcedon, an instinctive though inarticulate sense that Christ has two wills,
which the monotheletes challenged by inventing a new variety of Apollinarianism
that denied him a human faculty of will; this was condemned, and orthodoxy
re-established. The true picture, however, is that both the tradition inherited
from the fourth century and the post-Nestorian consensus agreed on a view of
Christ that did not deny him a rational will but gave it nothing to do and
rarely referred to it. Whether there was talk of ‘one will’ or ‘two wills’ made
no difference – until Maximus the Confessor came up with a new interpretation of
Gethsemane and thereby of the operation of will(s) in Christ. His solution was
not adopted at Constantinople III, but subsequently found its way into the
orthodox tradition.23 Such representation
of real development as simply the preservation of traditional doctrine against
heretical innovation has, of course, been a recurrent phenomenon in the history
of Christianity. Because it actually facilitates innovation, we may allow it to
theologians – but not, surely, to historians.
19 E.g.
Cyril, Hom. on
Luke 146, transl. R. P. Smith (Studion, 1983), 582f.; and Quod unus sit Christus
(772D), in: Deux dialogues christologiques, SC 97 (Paris, 1964),
494.
20 Published
by Marcel Richard in Polychronion, Festschrift F. Dölger (Heidelberg,
1966), 431-40; reprinted in id., Opera Minora III, §65. See esp.
436-8.
21 The Lateran
Council of 649 did better: Pope Martin in his final speech, just before the approval
of the canons, stressed the obedience of the human nature to the passion –
attributed, be it noted, not to the human nature as a distinct subject but to
the incarnate Word acting ‘humanly’ (1, pp. 360-5). But of course the modern
view is that the Acts of 649 were largely composed (before the council even
met!) by Maximus himself and other Greek monks; see Rudolf Riedinger, Die
Lateransynode von 649 und Maximos der Bekenner, in: F. Heinzer and C. Schönborn
(eds.), Maximus Confessor: Actes du Symposium sur Maxime le Confesseur,
Fribourg, 2-5 Septembre 1980 (Fribourg, 1982), 111-21.
22 See
F.-M. Léthel, Théologie (1979), 92-9.
23 John
of Damascus in his treatment of Christ’s wills in On the orthodox faith combines
an admirably lucid summary of St Maximus’ position with echoes of the more
traditional position, e.g.: ‘He wills not only those things which he
willed naturally as God (for it is no part of Godhead to will to eat and drink
and the like), but also those things that support human nature, and this not
through opposition in choice (gnEmj) but through the individuality of the
natures. For he willed naturally in this way when his divine volition willed it
and permitted the flesh to suffer and do what was proper to it’ (Expositio
fidei, ed. Bonifatius Kotter, Berlin 1973, 139, 50-4).
No comments:
Post a Comment