Immediate
Hominization from the Systems Perspective
Rev. Nicanor Pier
Giorgio Austriaco, O.P.
Introduction
Jean Porter
has claimed that the apparent change this past century in the Catholic Church’s
position regarding the origins of the human person has left Catholics without a
systematic metaphysical account that supports the fully personal status of very
early-stage human embryos.1 Her argument is relatively straightforward. Before
the twentieth century, the Church officially taught that early abortion was not
considered the killing of a human being—though it remained gravely evil—because
the magisterium believed that the unformed fetus was not a human person in the
full sense of the word.2 According to Porter, this perspective was based, not primarily
upon flawed medieval embryology, but upon a metaphysical account of the human
person grounded in the hylomorphic theory associated with Aristotle and St. Thomas
Aquinas. More specifically, she maintains that this perspective logically flowed
from the important metaphysical principle found in hylomorphism that matter has
to be disposed to receive a particular kind of soul.3 Hence, for both
the Peripatetic Philosopher and the Angelic Doctor (and the Catholic Church
which followed them), a human, rational soul cannot inform a body unless that
body possesses a level of complexity and organization appropriate to that form
of life. This is the theory of delayed hominization.4
In contrast,
today, the Catholic Church, pointing to advances in the biological sciences for
justification, teaches that procured abortion extending from conception to
birth is murder.5 Though the magisterium has not expressly committed
itself to an affirmation of a philosophical nature regarding the ensoulment of
the human person,6 Porter argues—correctly, in my opinion—that this
current perspective favors a theory of immediate hominization that attributes
personhood to the earliest stages of human embryonic life. If this is true,
however, has the Church, in implicitly rejecting the theory of delayed
hominization, not also rejected the hylomorphism on which this theory stands?
More specifically, Porter asks, has the Church, in favoring immediate hominization,
not also rejected the metaphysical principle that matter has to be disposed to
form? At first glance, the one-celled human embryo does not appear to be
sufficiently organized to be disposed to the human form and so to have a rational
soul. Whether it is, is certainly debatable. Thus, Porter concludes that
differences between defenders of delayed and immediate hominization involve
“fundamental philosophical and theological issues that do not depend on
scientific facts in any obvious and non-question-begging way.”7 In other words,
in her eyes, the theory of immediate hominization does not appear to cohere
with the classical hylomorphic account of the human person that is presupposed
by much of the Catholic tradition. Hence, her challenge to Catholics is that
they reconcile what Porter considers the sound and compelling philosophical
principles of Aristotelian-Thomistic hylomorphism with the modern scientific
account of embryogenesis that undergirds the Church’s current teaching on the
origin of the human person at conception.
Though there
is much that can be disputed in Porter’s essay, her central thesis that
Catholics would benefit from a scientifically sophisticated and robust
metaphysical account of the human person seems to be correct. How are we to
talk about a human “soul,” human “nature,” or the “disposition of matter” in
this new century, which some have already predicted will be the century of
biology? Even within Catholic circles, a lack of a metaphysical account of the
person that properly acknowledges the advances of molecular biology and
genomics has led to much controversy on bioethical issues both at the
beginning-of-life and at the end-of-life.8
To contribute
to this ongoing debate, this paper will develop a metaphysical account of the
human person using insights taken from the emerging discipline of systems
biology.9 It
opens with an overview of this new, and for most people, still unfamiliar
scientific perspective. However, as we shall note below, hylomorphism remains a
potent description of living things. Good science cannot replace good philosophy.
Thus, the systems perspective that will be described here will presuppose the
basic conceptual framework outlined by Aristotle and St. Thomas. It does not
even attempt to demonstrate the existence of souls or substances or natures. Rather,
the systems perspective represents one attempt to translate the terms and concepts
used by the Catholic tradition into a modern idiom that brings together the commonplace
intuitions of everyman with the experimental insights of the twentyfirst century
biologist. It seeks to account for the integrity, dynamism, and identity of the
human organism in a way that is comprehensible to today’s scientifically sophisticated
audience. Porter has challenged Catholics to reconcile a theory of immediate hominization
with the philosophical principles that are rooted in their own tradition. The
systems perspective is one possible response to her challenge. It reformulates hylomorphic
theory in light of recent scientific discoveries and in doing so, justifies a
theory of immediate hominization that embraces the fully personal status of the
very early-stage human embryo.
1 Jean Porter,
“Is the Embryo a Person? Arguing with the Catholic Traditions,” Commonweal 129.3
(February 8, 2002): 8-10.
2 For an
extensive history of the Catholic Church’s teaching on abortion, see John R. Connery,
S.J., Abortion: The Development of the Roman Catholic Perspective (Chicago:
Loyola Press, 1977).
3 Thomas
Aquinas, Summa Theologiae (New York: Benziger Brothers, 1947), I. Q.
76.5, replies 1, 3.
4 For a now
classic exposition of the theory of delayed hominization, see Joseph F. Donceel,
S.J., “Immediate Animation and Delayed Hominization,” Theological Studies 31.1
(1970): 76–105. For a response, see Benedict Ashley, O.P., “A Critique of the
Theory of Delayed Hominization,” in An Ethical Evaluation of Fetal
Experimentation, ed. Donald G. McCarthy and Albert S. Moraczewski, O.P.
(St. Louis, MO: Pope John XXIII Center, 1976), 113–133. Also see the essay of
Jean de Siebenthal, “L’animation selon Thomas d’Aquin: Peut-on affirmer que
l’embryon est d’abord autre chose qu’un homme en s’appuyant sur Thomas
d’Aquin?” in L’Embryon: Un homme. Actes du Congres de Lausanne 1986 (Lausanne:
Societe suisse de bioethique, 1986), 91–98, summarized in W. May, Catholic
Bioethics and the Gift of Human Life (Huntington, IN: Our Sunday
Visitor, 2000), 164–165.
5 “[P]rocured
abortion is the deliberate and direct killing, by whatever means it is carried out,
of a human being in the initial phase of his or her existence, extending from
conception to birth. The moral gravity of procured abortion is apparent in all
its truth if we recognize that we are dealing with murder.” John Paul II, Evangelium
vitae, n. 58, http://www.vatican.va/ holy_father/john_paul_ii/encyclicals/documents/hf_jp_ii_enc_
25031995_evangeliumvitae_en.html.
6 Sacred
Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith, Donum vitae, I.1, http://www.vatican.va/roman_curia/congregations/cfaith/documents/rc_con_cfaith_doc_19870222_respect-for-human-life_en.html.
Also see Sacred Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith, Declaration on
Procured Abortion, note 19, http://www.vatican.va/roman_curia/congregations/cfaith/documents/rc_con_cfaith_doc_19741118_declaration-abortion_en.html.
7 Porter, “Is
the Embryo a Person?” 9.
8 As discussed
in this paper, Catholic thinkers disagree on how one is to understand the
ensoulment of a human being. At the end of life, on the other hand, there is
also disagreement on how one is to understand and define death. For a taste of
this second debate, compare Edward J. Furton, “Brain Death, the Soul, and
Organic Life,” National Catholic Bioethics Quarterly 2.3 (Autumn
2002): 455–470, with D. Alan Shewmon, “The Brain and Somatic Integration:
Insights into the Standard Biological Rationale for Equating ‘Brain Death’ with
Death,” Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 26.5 (October 2001): 457–478.
9 This paper
continues to develop and explore the systems perspective first proposed in my
essay, “On Static Eggs and Dynamic Embryos: A Systems Perspective,” National
Catholic Bioethics Quarterly 2.4 (Winter 2002): 659–683. The text for
the section that follows (“The Systems Perspective”) is taken, in modified form,
from this published work.
The
Systems Perspective
A product of
the post-genomic explosion in biological information, systems biology is an
emerging field of research that seeks to understand the living whole as a
dynamic network of integrated parts.10 Its goal is to uncover the fundamental design
principles of living systems by looking at what system theorists call a
system’s structure and its dynamics. An analysis of a system’s structure
identifies all the parts of the system and describes their interactions. In
biology, this would involve cataloging all the molecules that go into
assembling a living organism and then determining which ones interact with each
other. An analysis of a system’s dynamics focuses on the behavior of these
interacting molecules over time. In biology, this would involve questions
regarding growth, development, and maintenance of the living organism. As will
be discussed below, the structure and the dynamics of a living system are
inseparably interdependent. A living system is always molecules in motion.
Thus, the most important question for the systems biologist is how both the structure
and dynamics of a living system together give rise to the physical properties and
visible behavior of the organism.
The two
insights of systems biology that are of particular interest to us here as we
update classical hylomorphism are its emphases on the holism of the living
organism and the determinism of animal development. First, the emphasis on
holism. Consider the human body. The most common view is to see the human being
as a collection of organs working together under the sway of the central
nervous system. Another approach is to see the body as an organized collection
of 73 trillion cells of different kinds—nerve cells, heart cells, or skin cells,
just to name a few of the approximately 260 cell types in the human body—all working
together in the organic whole. However, the more radical perspective offered by
systems biology is to see the human organism as a dynamic, complex, and seamlessly
integrated network not of organs or cells but of molecules, including
DNA, RNA, lipids, metabolites, and proteins, connected by reaction pathways
which generate shape, mass, energy, and information transfer over the course of
a human lifetime. In contrast to the first two prevailing reductionistic and
mechanistic views mentioned above, the organism is seen here as a single,
unified whole, a complex and dynamic network of interacting molecules that
appear and then disappear in time. It is an embodied process that has both
spatial and temporal manifestations.
To illustrate
the holistic perspective, we turn to a symphonic orchestra. One way to view a
classical orchestra would be to say that it is made up of four groups of
musicians playing a type of instrument: woodwind, brass, percussion, or string.
Another is to say that it is made up of approximately ninety musicians. The
systems view would be to see it as a single dynamic network of interacting
parts where the whole is greater than the sum of the parts. Since each musician
has an instrument and a score (and these could also each be counted as discrete
‘parts’), the orchestra at a minimum has 270 parts, all organized and seamlessly
integrated into a single unity that produces music. In fact, from the systems perspective,
an orchestra is not truly an orchestra until its parts begin to interact with
one another; i.e., when it is performing a symphony. Therefore, to see the living
organism as a dynamic system is to see it as a symphonic whole, where DNA, RNA,
lipids, and protein molecules, like musicians and their instruments, appear and
then disappear on stage in the choreographed performance called life.
As noted
above, systems biology, in addition to emphasizing the holism of the organism,
also underscores the deterministic nature of animal development. In this, there
is a crucial difference between an orchestra and an organism. One orchestra can
play many symphonies, because the musical score determines how and when the
different parts will interact. In other words, the same structure can give rise
to different dynamics—the same parts of one orchestra can interact in different
ways to produce either Beethoven’s Ninth Symphony or Mozart’s Symphony No. 40. Thus,
one cannot predict the future performance of an orchestra from simply studying its
parts. It is an indeterminate system. An organism, on the other hand, is a deterministic
system that follows a particular developmental trajectory. In other words,
there is a causal relationship between the past, present, and future states of a
living system because the molecular composition of the organism constrains the possible
sequence of ordered transformations through which the system can advance. A
puppy cannot grow into an ostrich.
In this
deterministic view, an organism changes and progresses through a sequence of
ordered molecular changes precisely because each subsequent step in a reaction
pathway is driven by the products of the previous step. Consequently, from the
systems perspective, every developmental change, including the teething of an infant
or the sexual maturation of a teenager, can be traced to necessary
transformations in the molecular composition of that particular human
individual. In the end, the trajectory of animal development is like a falling
chain of molecular dominoes that manifests itself as outward physical changes
in the organism. Once the process begins, it is a self-driven,
self-perpetuating chain reaction of molecular transformations that continues
throughout the life span of the animal.
Finally, let
me emphasize here that the determinism of the biological process that drives
development does not rule out the very real effects of the environment on the
living organism. From the systems perspective, at any given point in time, the development
of an organism is determined because at that point in time its molecular network
can only change in one way. However, not all the molecules in the network are
derived from the genome. In fact, most of them are derived from the
environment. Approximately 66 percent of the human body, for instance, is made
up of water molecules. Thus, it should be no surprise to anyone that an
individual raised in the calorically restricted environment of Somalia would
look different from the individual’s identical twin raised in the calorically affluent
United States. Nurture influences nature.11 Nevertheless, the genetic constitution of the
organism still does constrain its developmental possibilities in a fixed and
species-specific manner. Regardless of their childhood homes, the physical resemblance
between the African and his American twin would still be striking.
10 For concise
overviews of systems biology, see L. Hartwell et al., “From Molecular to Modular
Cell Biology,” Nature 402.6761 Suppl. (December 2, 1999): C47–52, and Hiroaki Kitano,
“Systems Biology: A Brief Overview,” Science 295.5560 (March 1, 2002):
1662–1664. Good introductions to different aspects of the systems perspective
written for the nonspecialist can be found in Stuart Kauffman, At Home in the
Universe (New York: Oxford University Press, 1995) and Albert-Laszlo Barabasi,
Linked: The New Science of Networks (Cambridge, MA: Perseus Publishing, 2002).
11 For an
insightful discussion of the interrelationship between nature and nurture, see
Matt Ridley, Nature Via Nurture: Genes, Experience, and What Makes Us Human
(New York: HarperCollins, 2003).
Systems
Hylomorphism: The Human Organism from the Systems Perspective
With an
overview of the systems perspective in mind, we can now begin constructing a
systems-based description of the human organism. The primary challenge for this
task will be to explain the stable dynamism of a being that is able to maintain
its integrity and its identity over a period that can last up to a century.
This is a real stability despite the numerous kinetic and metabolic studies
using a variety of experimental techniques that have shown that 98 percent of
the atoms of the adult human body, including those found in the brain and
nervous system, are replaced in about two years.12 How are we to reconcile both these observations? To put
it another way, the human organism is a being that has an origin, undergoes biological
development, and then dies. It is always changing but still remains the same. How
is this so? An adequate philosophical anthropology would have to explain this
stable dynamism.
As Porter has
correctly noted, however, a coherent and compelling philosophical solution to
the challenge of describing the human being already exists in the hylomorphic
theory of Aristotle and St. Thomas Aquinas. She is not alone in this assessment.
In their book, Body & Soul, Protestant philosophers J.P. Moreland
and Scott B. Rae also defend hylomorphism (which they call Thomistic dualism)
as the most coherent explanation for the human being.13 As we shall
see in brief below, I believe these authors are correct—hylomorphism is already
able to adequately explain the stability and the change found in living things.
There is no need to re-invent the wheel. The theory simply needs to be updated
in light of recent scientific advances.
Thus, as
mentioned in the introduction, in constructing a scientifically informed description
of the human being, the approach we use here will be to weave together the
basic principles of Aristotelian-Thomistic hylomorphism and the insights of the
systems perspective.14
Before
turning to a systems-based analysis of the human being, we begin with a basic
review of hylomorphism.15 First proposed by Aristotle, and developed by his disciples,
especially St. Thomas Aquinas, hylomorphic theory sought to explain the nature
of things and the nature of their changes. In brief, for the Aristotelian
tradition, all things—especially all living things—are substances composed of
both a formal and a material principle. The formal principle, also called the
substantial form or, in living things, the soul, constitutes every being as a specific
kind of thing with specific causal powers, those powers that allow it to be a
particular kind of thing and to do what that kind of thing does. In the
biological realm, it gives the creature its stability, its unity, and its
identity. It structures the organism, determines its nature, and specifies its
end. The matter, on the other hand, is the corresponding principle of potency
that the form determines or actualizes. According to the hylomorphic theory, both
matter and form are inseparable.16 Together both constitute a stable substance.
Stable
substances, however, often change. For the Aristotelians, change involved the
replacement of form. This process happens in two ways, corresponding to the two
types of change evident in the world. First, there is substantial change, which
radically alters the identity of the thing. Substantial changes involve the
replacement of one substantial form with another in matter that is properly
disposed to receive the new form. The classic example of this type of change
involves the death of an organism, where, say, the form of a living dog is
replaced by the individual forms of the elements in the dog’s carcass. Next, there
is accidental change, which only modifies a thing without changing its nature.
This kind of change involves the replacement of one accidental form with
another, again, in matter that is properly disposed to receive the new form. An
example of this type of change involves the growth in size of an organism.
Thus, according to hylomorphism, all change observable in nature can be
accounted for by invoking the replacement of forms in properly disposed matter.
Note that during accidental changes, the substantial form or soul remains,
ensuring the integrity and identity of the organism. This explains well the
stable dynamism of the human being. A man is stable because of his substantial form,
yet he is dynamic because he is capable of changing his accidental forms.
We now turn
to the systems perspective. How are we to talk about a human “soul,” human
“nature,” or the “disposition of matter” in a scientifically informed manner?
In other words, how are we to translate classical hylomorphism into a modern
idiom? To begin, we should note that the systems perspective, like the hylomorphic
perspective, is a substantial perspective; i.e., it affirms the existence of bona
fide substances in the world.17 The organism is seen here as a single, unified network
of interacting molecules that is organized in a species-specific manner. Here,
the whole is greater than the sum of the parts. A typical 70-kilogram man is made
up primarily of oxygen (43 kg), carbon (16 kg), hydrogen (7 kg), nitrogen (1.8 kg),
and calcium (1 kg).18 However, what makes this reference man radically
different from a 68.8-kg pile of these five elements is that in his case, the
elements are organized and interact in a particular way, a species-specific
way. Indeed, a snapshot of the human body at any point in time would reveal an
intricate net of molecular interactions distributed in three-dimensional space.
From the systems perspective, this particular pattern, this organization of the
molecules of the human being, would be a manifestation of his immaterial soul.19
To see how
the network of molecular interactions can be said to reflect and manifest the
soul, note the parallels between three functions associated with this network
and the three functions traditionally associated with the formal principle of an
organism. First, the soul makes an organism what it is and determines its end. From
a physiological perspective, the net of molecular interactions makes the man what
he is and distinguishes him from a lion or a lima bean plant or some other
living thing. Furthermore, since life is a deterministic process of molecular
transformations, these molecular interactions also define his developmental
trajectory and determine his biological end. Second, the soul unifies and integrates
an organism, maintaining its identity through changes. As noted above, the
human body is in a constant state of molecular flux. Every two years, nearly
all of its atoms are replaced. However, the pattern of the molecular
interactions remains the same, providing a ground for the substantial unity and
identity of an individual with a life span of eighty or more years. Finally, to
the ancients, the soul is the source for the powers and capacities of the
organism. It is the principle of the being’s nature. Analogously, the net of molecular
interactions can also be said to ground the human being’s physiological capacities.
To illustrate this, everyone knows that a man is able to see because he has
eyes. However, from the systems perspective a man only has eyes because there
are molecules in his body that interact to form these eyes. Thus, in the lingo
of systems theory, vision is a capacity that emerges from the network of
molecular interactions that define the man as a human being.20 It is also
rooted in the soul. With all this in mind, it should be easy to see how the
systems perspective can envision a human being as a substance consisting of
informed matter, here seen as a single dynamic system of molecules organized in
a species-specific configuration.
However, how
then do we account for change? If all change simply involves the rearrangement
of atoms, does this mean that change can only be of the accidental variety? Not
quite. To see how the systems perspective understands hylomorphic substantial
and accidental change, we have to first discuss several aspects of the structure
of living systems. As a dynamic system, the living organism is a robust system.
In other words, it is able to maintain its function in spite of the loss or breakdown
of one or even many of its individual components. For example, it is not uncommon
to find persons who live normal lives with several mutated genes. Systems theorists
have discovered that this robustness, this high tolerance for error, arises
from the particular topology or structure of natural systems.21 They are
organized in such a way that the molecules are related to each other in a
hub-spoke network analogous to the route network of any airline. A few
molecules are highly connected to other molecules—they are the hubs of the
living network, just as major airports in Chicago or Atlanta are the hubs for
several U.S. airline route systems—while the rest of the molecules are only
peripherally connected to a few other molecules—these are equivalent to the
smaller airports often found in less populated states.
In this type
of hub-spoke system,22 two types of change are possible. First, there are
changes that involve the addition or the removal of molecules that lead to alterations
in the behavior of the network without changing its overall shape or trajectory.
These involve the loss or addition of peripheral molecules in the network, and
would be equivalent to shutting down a small and relatively isolated airport in
Fargo, ND, or opening a new one in Statesboro, Georgia. These changes do not affect
the overall network of air traffic in the country. Indeed, even the loss or addition
of several small nodes would not change the overall pattern of the system. Similarly,
in a living system, one could lose or add different kinds of peripheral
molecules to the network without changing its fundamental structure. A human
being, for example, could lose or gain weight. Despite these molecular changes,
however, the basic framework of the organism and its developmental trajectory
remain intact. This type of molecular change would be the systems analog to
Aristotelian-Thomistic accidental change.
In contrast,
there are changes that involve the addition or removal of molecules that lead
to system collapse. This would involve the loss or addition of well connected
molecules and would be equivalent either to shutting down an airport like Chicago’s
O’Hare or the sudden opening of a new hub in Boston’s Logan Airport. Both would
produce chaotic conditions that could even lead to the collapse of the entire
national air traffic system. Similarly, in a living system, the loss of a hub molecule
either by genetic mutation or inactivation by a poison like cyanide would lead
to a loss of the integrity of the network. Losing these molecules would be equivalent
to generating gaps in a row of toppling dominoes. The chain reaction stops, the
network collapses, and the organism dies. This type of molecular change that
alters the very nature of the being would be the systems analog to
Aristotelian-Thomistic substantial change.
To summarize,
the systems perspective described here represents one attempt to reformulate
the received philosophical framework of classical hylomorphism so that it
incorporates the insights of modern biology. Here, the human organism is a substantial
being, a dynamic network of molecules now existing not as independent molecules
per se but as different parts of one human organism. This
speciesspecific network, which is distributed in three-dimensional space and is
able to interact over time in the deterministic process that we call human
development, is a manifestation of the human being’s formal principle, his immaterial
soul. It is the soul that makes a man a human being by organizing the matter,
determining his identity and stability, and specifying his biological end.
Further, all change observable during development, both substantial and
accidental, can be accounted for by invoking the replacement of forms
manifested as changes in the molecular interactions within dynamic systems.
One more
point needs to be made. In the Aristotelian worldview adopted by St. Thomas,
there were three generic kinds of souls, each characterized by its ca pacities
and powers. Associated with plants, Aristotle taught that the lowest type of soul
is the nutritive or vegetative soul, which enables an organism to grow and reproduce.23 Next,
associated with animals, there is the sensitive or animal soul, which, in
addition to the powers of the nutritive soul, also enables an organism to sense
and to desire.24 Finally, associated with human beings, there is the
human or rational soul, which, in addition to the powers of the vegetative and
animal souls, enables an organism to think and to will.
Recent
advances in biology, however, have shown that this perspective may have to be
modified. Today, it is becoming clear that it is likely that all organisms, plants
and animals included, communicate with each other and with other living beings
in order to achieve particular ends. The work of three laboratories is
particularly illuminating. First, Ian Baldwin and his colleagues in Germany
were able to show that the common desert plant Nicotiana attenuata is
able to specifically recognize the larvae of a particular predator
insect that is tolerant to some of its chemical defenses, and to modify its
physiology accordingly.25 Further, this recognition is immediate, as
evidenced by a physiological change that is propagated throughout the damaged
leaf ahead of the rapidly foraging herbivore.26 Next, Meiners and Hilker, also in Germany, have
demonstrated that egg laying by a herbivore beetle induces the elm tree to
release organic compounds in the air which attract other insects that prey on
these eggs.27
Finally, and most spectacularly, Arimura et al., in Japan, have
demonstrated that lima bean plants communicate with each other and with
insects.28 These
authors showed that a lima bean plant that is under attack by spider mites
emits volatile substances that prompt neighboring and distant lima bean plants
to undergo physiological changes, that will protect them from a future attack of
these mites. Furthermore, they also demonstrated that this same plant when it
is being attacked emits signals that attract predatory mites that will feed
upon the original infestation of spider mites. These studies are only a sample
of many that demonstrate that it is becoming increasingly difficult to distinguish
plants and animals as the ancients did.29 Both plants and animals grow, reproduce, and interact
with other organisms in the biosphere. All organisms affect and are affected by
each other. Plants can respond to touch, and in a primitive manner, they can
also smell. Thus, to different degrees, both plants and animals are able to
sense as the ancients understood these actions. Apparently, both plants and
animals have souls with both nutritive and sensitive powers.
But how then
are we to distinguish different types of souls? Are there only two generic
kinds of souls in the world, i.e., rational, and thus, human, and nonrational
but sensitive, and thus nonhuman? As noted above, from the systems perspective,
the soul of any organism manifests itself as a species-specific network of
molecular interactions. From this, it follows that one reasonable way of
classifying souls is to emphasize, as the ancients perhaps did not, that there
are as many different kinds of souls as there are natural species of living
things—a human soul animates a man, a lion soul animates a lion, and a lima
bean soul animates a lima bean plant.30 The importance of this point will become evident
below.
12 For details,
see my essay, “The Pre-implantation Embryo Revisited: A Two-celled Individual
or Two Individual Cells?” Linacre Quarterly 70.2 (May 2003): 121–126.
13 James Porter
Moreland and Scott B. Rae, Body & Soul: Human Nature & the Crisis in
Ethics (Downers Grove, IL: InterVarsity Press, 2000).
14 This approach
is particularly attractive to the Catholic tradition, which committed itself to
Aristotelian-Thomistic language in 1312 when the Council of Vienne defined de
fide that the human soul is the form of the body. Henricus Denziger and
Adolfus Schonmetzer, eds., Enchiridion Symbolorum: Definitionem et
Declarationum de Rebus Fidei et Morum (New York: Herder and Herder, 1965),
n. 902; see also Catechism of the Catholic Church, 2nd ed.,
trans. United States Conference of Catholic Bishops (Vatican City: Libreria
Editrice Vaticana, 1997), n. 365.
15 For a good
summary of classical hylomorphic theory, also see William A. Wallace, O.P., The
Elements of Philosophy: a Compendium for Philosophers and Theologians (New York:
Alba House, 1977), 41–84.
16 The human
form or soul is an exception to this rule, since it can exist apart from the material
principle. However, as so existing, it is not a complete person. For
discussion, see Anton C. Pegis, St. Thomas and the Problem of the Soul in
the Thirteenth Century (Toronto, Canada: Pontifical Institute of Medieval
Studies, 1934).
17 As noted
earlier, the systems perspective presented here presupposes the metaphysical framework
put forward by classical hylomorphic theory. Given the dynamic nature of the
human body, which is continually undergoing molecular change, anyone who
rejects the distinction between living substances and nonliving aggregates
would have to conclude that he or she can only exist and be identified as a
distinct and unique human individual for a maximum of two years. This, I
believe, is obviously ludicrous. For a modern defense of the substantiality of
the human person, see J.P. Moreland and John Mitchell, “Is the Human Person a
Substance or a Property-thing?” Ethics & Medicine 11.3 (Fall 1995):
50–55.
18 Body
composition data was obtained from Report of the Task Group on Reference Man
(International Commission on Radiological Protection No. 23: A Report)
(Burlington, MA: Elsevier Science and Technology Books, 1975).
19 Again,
systems hylomorphism presupposes the classical conviction that the human soul
is immaterial and subsistent. For a clear summary of the arguments for this
view, see Brian J. Shanley, O.P., The Thomist Tradition (Dordrecht: Kluwer
Academic Publishers, 2002), 153–166.
20 For a
nontechnical discussion of emergence and the emergent properties of different systems,
see Steven Johnson, Emergence: The Connected Lives of Ants, Brains, Cities,
and Software (New York: Scribner, 2001). For a philosophical analysis,
see Timothy O’Conner, “Emergent Properties,” American Philosophical
Quarterly 31.2 (1994): 91–104.
21 For two
recent studies on the robustness of biological systems, see Andreas Wagner, “Robustness
against Mutations in Genetic Networks of Yeast,” Nature Genetics 24.4
(April 2000): 355–361; and Z. Gu et al., “Role of Duplicate Genes in Genetic
Robustness against Null Mutations,” Nature 421.6918 (January 2, 2003):
63–66.
22 In the jargon
of systems theory, the hub-spoke system is called a scale-free network. For a
review, see Z. N. Oltvai and A. L. Barabasi, “Systems Biology: Life’s
Complexity Pyramid,” Science 298.5594 (October 25, 2002): 763–764. For
recent studies involving scale-free networks in living systems, see H. Jeong et
al., “Lethality and Centrality in Protein Networks,” Nature 411.6833 (May 3,
2001): 41–42; E. Ravasz et al., “Hierarchical Organization of Modularity in
Metabolic Networks,” Science 297.5586 (August 30, 2002): 1551–1555; and J. J.
Han et al., “Evidence for Dynamically Organized Modularity in the Yeast
Protein-Protein Interaction Network,” Nature 430.6995 (July 1, 2004): 88–93.
23 “For this
reason all plants too are thought to live; for they evidently have in them such
a potentiality and first principle, through which they come to grow and decay
in opposite directions. For they do not grow upwards without growing downwards,
but they grow in both directions alike and in every direction—this being so of
all that are constantly nourished and continue to live, as long as they are
able to receive nourishment … This is obvious in the case of plants; for they
have no other potentiality of soul.” Aristotle, De Anima, 413
a25–33. All citations are taken from Aristotle, De Anima: Books II and III,
trans. D.W. Hamlyn (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993).
24 “But it is
because of sense-perception first of all that [living things] will be animal,
for even those things which do not move or change their place, but which do
have senseperception, we speak of as animals and not merely as living.”
Aristotle, De Anima: Books II and III, 413 b2–3; “Plants have the
nutritive faculty only; other creatures have both this and the faculty of
sense-perception. And if that of sense-perception, then that of desire also;
for desire comprises wanting, passion, and wishing.” Aristotle, De Anima:
Books II and III, 414 a32–35.
25 J. Kahl et
al., “Herbivore-induced Ethylene Suppresses a Direct Defense but Not a Putative
Indirect Defense against an Adapted Herbivore,” Planta 210.2 (January
2000): 336–342.
26 U. Schittko,
C. A. Preston, and I. T. Baldwin, “Eating the Evidence? Manduca sexta Larvae
Cannot Disrupt Specific Jasmonate Induction in Nicotiana attenuata by
Rapid Consumption,” Planta 210.2 (January 2000): 343–346.
27 Torsten
Meiners and Monika Hilker, “Induction of Plant Synomones by Oviposition of a
Phytophagous Insect,” Journal of Chemical Ecology 26.1 (January 2000):
221–232.
28 G. Arimura et
al., “Herbivory-Induced Volatiles Elicit Defence Genes in Lima Bean Leaves,” Nature
406.6795 (August 3, 2000): 511–515.
29 For a review
of plant-plant and plant-insect communication, see Edward E. Farmer, “Surface-to-Air
Signals,” Nature 411.6839 (June 14, 2001): 854–856.
30 As both
Aristotle and St. Thomas acknowledged, there is no generic animal or generic plant
soul. Rather, each animal or plant soul is a particular kind of animal or plant
soul depending upon the particular animal or plant species it informed. For
example, St. Thomas speaks of the form of a horse, forma equi, (Sentences,
Ia, 36, 2, ar. 2., ad. 2) and the form of wood, forma substantialis ligni,
(Sentences IV, 10, 1, 3, co, line 34) in the mind of God. Significantly,
he does not talk about an animal form incidentally specified as horse,
or a plant form incidentally specified as wood. I thank Fr. Michael Dodds,
O.P., for pointing this out to me. Thomas Aquinas, Sentences, Opera
Omnia, vol. 6 (Parma: Typis Petri Fiaccadori, 1856).
Hominization
from the Systems Perspective
Jean Porter
has asked for a scientifically sophisticated philosophical account of the human
being that respects classical hylomorphic theory. The systems perspective described
here is one possible response to this challenge. It is a holistic account of
living substances that recognizes the molecular basis for life. However, Porter
has also asked for a philosophical account that can justify a theory of
immediate hominization. To successfully accomplish this charge, the systems
perspective has to explain three things. First, it needs to show how
fertilization is an animation event that involves the appearance of a new soul
unlike the soul of either the egg or the sperm. Second, it needs to show that
this soul in the human zygote is, in fact, the same soul found in the mature
human adult. Third, it has to show how both these previous facts support an
argument for the personhood of the very earliest human embryo.
First, there
is the animation event that is fertilization. As I have argued in detail elsewhere,
the systems perspective highlights the seamless unity of the developmental process
that begins with conception and ends with the death of the organism.31 In brief, when
the sperm and the egg fuse at fertilization, new molecules are introduced into
the egg, radically changing it. Indeed, since the egg now has a new structure,
it is in fact a new system. It is now an embryo. As explained above, the composition
and the behavior of a deterministic system are necessarily linked. Thus, in
addition to changing the structure of the egg, fertilization also triggers a
change in its dynamics, by reorganizing and activating the interconnected
network of inert maternal molecules that make up most of its contents. This
initiates the chain of reactions and molecular interactions that drive cell
division and differentiation. In the absence of anything to disrupt it, this
self-driven, self-perpetuating process of molecular interactions will continue
for nine months and beyond, transforming the living system called the embryo
into the living system called a healthy eight-pound baby. Whereas the egg
before fertilization had a life span of only twenty-four hours, the embryo
after fertilization now has a span of seventy or more years. Thus, from the
systems perspective, fertilization involves the transformation of one static
network into a dynamic one. However, since networks are manifestations of
souls, a new network must reflect a new soul. At fertilization, the zygote is
animated by a new soul. It is animated in such a way that its subsequent
development is speciespredictable.
At this
point, we should note that Porter and others, pointing to the totipotency of
the cells that constitute the early mammalian embryo, have argued that the
early embryo is animated not by one soul but by several souls.32 They conclude
this because, in their view, the pre-implantation embryo lacks individuality.
To them, it is a ball of individual cells rather than a multi-celled individual.
As I have argued elsewhere, however, the most recent scientific evidence
demonstrates that the totipotent mammalian embryo is a single, integrated dynamic
system defined by a single set of embryonic axes.33 A single system reflects a single soul.
But what kind
of soul animates the zygote? In response, the systems perspective allows
one to see that calling the human organism an embryo, fetus, infant, teenager,
or adult is to arbitrarily label and distinguish certain segments of a continuous
chain of developmental events that do not differ in kind. Each is a different manifestation
of the same organism, the same living system, at a later stage of change. Each
is a different manifestation of the same molecular network. Each is a different
manifestation of the same soul, a human soul. From the systems perspective, once
development begins at fertilization, there simply is no place in a
deterministic process of molecular reactions for the series of substantial
changes envisioned by delayed hominization. Substantial change can occur only
at the onset of development because the organization of the molecules that drives
development and specifies the identity of the thing is established then. All change
after this point has to be accidental. Thus, at fertilization, the zygote is
animated by a human soul.
Finally, if
hominization occurs at fertilization, then the very earliest human embryos must
also be persons. To see this, recall that in the Catholic tradition, the commonly
accepted definition for personhood is that a person is an individual substance of
a rational nature.34 Note that according to this definition, personhood is
attributed to substances and says something about the nature of a thing. Thus,
every adult human being is a person, not simply because he has functions of
thinking and feeling but because he has a human nature that empowers him to
perform these functions.35 It is a nature grounded in his soul. However, as we
noted above, from the systems perspective, the human embryo has the same human
soul as the adult he will eventually develop into. Thus, the human embryo must
be as much a person as the human adult he will develop into, since both are the
same substance with the same nature. Accordingly, at fertilization, the zygote
is animated with a human soul, thus making him a substance with a human nature.
He is a person.
31 Austriaco,
“On Static Eggs,” 671–674.
32 For example,
see Jean Porter, “Individuality, Personal Identity, and the Moral Status of the
Preembryo: A Response to Mark Johnson,” Theological Studies 56 (1995):
763–770; Thomas A. Shannon and Allan B. Wolter, “Reflections on the Moral
Status of the Pre- Embryo,” Theological Studies 51.4 (December 1990):
603–626; and Lisa Cahill, “The Embryo and the Fetus: New Moral Contexts,” Theological
Studies 54.1 (March 1993): 124–142.
33 For details,
see my essay, “The Pre-implantation Embryo Revisited.”
34 This is the
Boethian definition of personhood that was embraced by the Western
philosophical tradition until the dawn of modernity (Boethius, De persona et
duabus naturis, vol. 64, ed. J.P. Migne [Paris: Patrologia Latina, 1847]; also
see St. Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologiae, Ia, 29, 1). Today, there is much
disagreement among philosophers and bioethicists on the proper definition of
personhood. As Ruth Macklin has noted, authors writing on the notion of
personhood fall into two camps: “low standard” and “high standard.” Low
standard personhood corresponds to those who believe that the embryo is a
person quite aside from brain function. High standard personhood corresponds to
those who believe that some form of self-consciousness is necessary to achieve
personhood. See her “Personhood in the Bioethics Literature,” Milbank Memorial
Fund Quarterly: Health and Society 61 (1983): 35–57. Metaphysically speaking,
these two categories correspond to those who equate personhood to the presence
of a human nature and those who equate personhood to the presence of certain
functions or capabilities. As many others have shown, the classical Boethian
definition of personhood presumed by the systems perspective can explain the
integrity and unity of the embodied human being experienced by the ordinary
individual. In contrast, those definitions that reject the personhood-as-nature
distinction inevitably lead either to substance dualism or the rejection of the
embodied experience of human persons.
For details,
see, for example, both Germain Grisez, “When Do People Begin?” Proceedings
of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 63 (1989): 27–47; and
Helen Watt, “The Origin of Persons,” in The Identity and Status of the Human
Embryo: Proceedings of the Third Assembly of the Pontifical Academy for
Life, eds. Juan de Dios Vial Correa and Elio Sgreccia (Vatican City:
Libreria Editrice Vaticana, 1999), 343–364.
35 In the same
way, the adult human male is a mammal, not because he can lactate and bear live
young, which he will never be able to do, but because he has a human nature
that empowers females of his species to perform these functions. For leading me
to this insight, I am indebted to Jenny Teichman in her article “The Definition
of ‘Person’,” Philosophy 60 (1985): 175–185.
Responding
to Possible Objections from Delayed Hominists
The most
significant change in classical hylomorphic theory advanced by the systems
perspective—and it is a change in emphasis rather than in substantial content—is
the proposal that we classify souls with species-based rather than generabased categories.
The human soul and every other kind of soul would be conceptualized here not
according to their generic powers, but by their specific power to organize the
molecular network that drives species-specific development. In other words,
from within the systems perspective, what makes a human soul human is neither
its power to think nor to will (though it would still have these of course) but
its power to organize a human body and to drive human development. In the same way,
a lion would have a lion soul that would have the power to organize a lion body
and to effect lion development. Therefore, there are as many kinds of souls as
there are natural species. With this move, the central concern of Porter and
other delayed hominists, that of identifying a biological substratum that can
properly support rationality and thus predispose the developing embryo to a
human, rational soul, becomes moot. Rather, within the context of systems hylomorphism,
matter is disposed to receive a soul when it contains all the molecules
required to give rise to the speciesspecific network that corresponds to a
particular type of soul. Thus, a human body is disposed to receive a human soul
at fertilization.
But Porter
and colleagues could object. They could contend that the move to reclassify
souls is an illegitimate one, because the three-category classification of souls
is an essential philosophical element of classical hylomorphic theory. As noted
above, however, classifying souls using species-specific rather than
genera-specific categories is not alien to the thought of either Aristotle or
Aquinas. Even delayed hominist Joseph Donceel, S.J., seems to assume that there
are forms of individual kinds of beasts.36 Furthermore, I could also respond to the objection by
pointing out that an even more basic philosophical principle in the Aristotelian-Thomistic
tradition is the conviction that philosophical analysis is dependent upon our
perception and experience of the real world. In other words, natural philosophy
relies upon and is governed by our observations of nature. For a case in point,
the three-category system of classifying souls was based upon Aristotle’s
observations of the living organisms around him. His observations convinced him
that plants do not interact with their environment as animals do. They simply
grew and reproduced. As noted above, however, current observations of this same
natural order strongly suggest that plants do indeed have capacities of
interacting with their environment that involve primitive sensitive and
appetitive powers. Thus, in light of this data, it is not unreasonable, and in
fact would be in accord with the tradition, to reclassify Aristotle’s generic
categories of souls to better reflect the reality of the world.
In response,
Porter and colleagues could suggest that all that is needed is a reformulation
of a genera-based classification of souls. For instance, William Wallace, O.P.,
who has advocated a theory of delayed hominization,37 has proposed a genera- based
classification of souls that defines an animal as an organism that not only senses
but also moves.38 However, this would be a modification of Aristotle’s
and St. Thomas’s view.39 Though this approach of reformulating a genera-based
classification is certainly feasible, it could still lead to some counter-intuitive
classifications whereby the apparently animal-like plants, the Venus flytrap (Dionaea
muscipula) and the touch-me-not (Mimosa pudica), could be
considered animals. In contrast, a species-based classification of souls would
avoid these problems. Further, it would also be the superior strategy, because
it has more explanatory power than its classical counterpart. Three advantages
immediately come to mind.
First,
systems hylomorphism solves the problem of explaining efficient causality during
embryogenesis. As Benedict Ashley, O.P., and Stephen J. Heaney have pointed
out, a modern theory of delayed hominization leaves this question unanswered: what
is the efficient cause that prepares the embryonic body to receive a rational
soul?40 According
to the classical Thomistic account, the embryonic body was brought to that
stage of organization just prior to its hominization by the vital spirit (virtus)
of the father working through his semen as an instrumental power. The semen,
for St. Thomas, remained as an active substance throughout the whole period of
preformation of the embryo.41 This was a crucial element of a classical theory of
delayed hominization. Today, as Ashley correctly notes, we know that the semen
does not even survive the first five days of embryonic development. However, without
the semen, what organizes the embryonic body? What prepares the embryo to
receive the rational soul? Porter and her fellow delayed hominists have not
responded to this critique.
Ashley has
suggested an alternative Thomistic theory that involves invoking a paternally
derived instrumental power that forms an embryo’s primary organ. This organ then
receives the instrumental power so that it acts as the body’s prime mover and
the efficient cause for embryogenesis.42 According to Ashley, in the zygote, the primary organ
is the nucleus with its genome. When this zygote divides and forms first the
blastula, and then the gastrula, the single primary organ would either be a cell
or patch of cells in the embryo that drives embryonic development. Eventually, these
cells which constitute the primary organ would develop into the nervous system and
then the brain. The problem with this proposal, however, is that experimental work
has shown that no single cell or group of cells in the early mammalian embryo
before the blastocyst stage has primacy over the other cells. No cell or group
of cells is indispensable for the continued development of the embryo. Rather, the
development of each cell is specified by the interactions among all the cells.43 Thus, if there is a primary organ responsible
for driving early embryonic development before the blastocyst stage, biologists
cannot find it. Moreover, I ask the question, What would drive the embryonic
development of the primary organ itself? Ashley proposes that the embryonic
primary organ is a patch of cells that is eventually transformed into the brain
and the nervous system. But what drives this process? Note that this
transformation is not simply a change in the size of the primary organ. Rather,
it involves the differentiation of a few relatively simple cells into a complex
structure made up of trillions of cells of diverse cell types. In fact, it is a
process of transformation not unlike the development of the embryo itself. From
his paper, it appears that Ashley presupposes that the primary organ can act as
the efficient cause for its own development. However, if this is the case,
could the embryo as a whole not do the same for itself?
Next, in
another reinterpretation of Thomistic embryology, Robert Pasnau has suggested
that from the scientific view, the virtus formativa begins to look very much
like the DNA present in every cell.44 I would argue, however, that this proposal undermines
the unity of the embryo: What coordinates the ten genomes, the ten separated virtus
formativa, in the embryo at the ten-cell morula stage?
In contrast,
a species-based classification of souls would properly respond to the problem
of efficient causality without raising other problematic questions: The parents
prepare the zygote for ensoulment through the action of their gametes. At fertilization,
the human soul that animates the zygote acts as a formal cause, making the
zygote a human embryo. Once it is formed, the human embryo, as an individual substance
with its own species-specific nature, would then drive its own development.
Here,
embryonic development would be attributed to the organism as a whole and not to
any single part of the developing embryo, in the same way that running is attributed
to the runner and not to his soul, his brain, or his legs. Putting it another way,
the embryo is the efficient cause of its own development in the same way that the
runner is the efficient cause of his running.
Second, the
move to reclassify souls would reconcile an apparent contradiction between the
philosophical perspective offered by hylomorphic theory and the scientific
perspective offered by developmental biology. Consider this: According to classical
hylomorphism, human development is a discontinuous process involving the
sequential appearance of three separate and distinct substances. First there is
the living being animated by a soul with vegetative powers, then there is the
living being animated by a soul with sensitive powers, and then there is the
living being animated by the rational soul. In contrast, according to modern developmental
biology, human development is a continuous process involving one living being
that is undergoing change. Porter asks for a philosophical argument that “will
convince our fellow citizens, most of whom know the facts as well as we do.”45 But one of
these hard facts is the organismal continuity of the developing human being!46 It is a fact that
leaves classical hylomorphism with its genera-based understanding of souls out in
the cold. In contrast, systems hylomorphism with its species-based
understanding of souls is able to acknowledge the temporal unity of the
developing organism—the developing human being is one throughout development
because it has one human soul—while retaining the basic framework of hylomorphism.
It is an explanation that out-explains its rival.
Finally, when
seen within a larger picture, a species-based classification of souls would
allow the philosopher of nature to ask questions not accessible to Aristotle or
to St. Thomas. For instance, when is the mouse embryo disposed to receive its
soul? Or when does a genetically engineered rice plant cease being rice? Or to put
it another way, when does genetic engineering change the disposition of matter such
that it cannot be informed by a rice soul? These and similar questions are becoming
more common-place and more complex in light of the rapidly growing field of
genomics and transgenic technology. A genera-based description of souls is simply
not capable of addressing these issues.
There is one
final objection that can be leveled against systems hylomorphism. One could
ask, Are the species differences upon which the framework is based any more
real than the apparent differences between animals and plants posited by Aristotle?
To respond, though some philosophers-of-science have doubted the reality of
biological species, the consensus among professional biologists is that the species
concept, the idea that there are distinct populations of organisms belonging to
a particular kind, is still a valid one. As Larry Arnhart has persuasively
argued, denying the historical permanence of species does not deny the reality
of species of natural kinds.47 Though evolutionary theory has demonstrated that
species are not eternally fixed, this does not make them any less real during
their time of existence. In the twentieth century, biologists have employed different
ways of classifying organisms, and when these various criteria coincide in identifying
individual organisms as belonging to one species, it is reasonable to regard
this species as a natural kind.48 Further, the natural reality of these species is confirmed
by the remarkable uniformity across cultures in the “folk classifications” of
species studied by biological anthropologists. Several studies have shown that
human beings around the world categorize plants and animals according to
universal regularities that reflect the natural order of living things.49 Natural
species and kinds do exist in the world.
36 “In order
that the idea of prime matter may be grasped, it may be useful to consider an
example. A cat kills and eats a mouse. The mouse is assimilated by the cat,
becomes part of the cat. During this process of assimilation something has
disappeared and something has persisted. When digested by the cat, the mouse is
no longer a mouse; its ‘mouseness,’ its substantial form, has disappeared. But
its prime matter persists. The prime matter is neither the cat nor the mouse;
it is not the dead mouse or the proteins or other chemicals which analysis may
discover in it. It is a principle of being which, when united to the
substantial form of a cat, constitutes a cat, and when combined with the
substantial form of a mouse, constitutes a mouse. It can never exist by itself,
it co-exists with the substantial form. What happened to the substantial form
of the mouse when the mouse was assimilated by the cat? Exactly what happens to
the roundness of the clay when you flatten the ball? The roundness disappears
exactly when and insofar as it is replaced by some other shape. In the same
way, the substantial form of the mouse disappears exactly when and insofar as
it is replaced by the substantial form of the cat. As it is impossible to
imagine a piece of clay existing without any shape, so it is impossible to
conceive prime matter existing without any substantial form.” See his Philosophical
Psychology (New York: Sheed and Ward, 1955), 6.
37 William A.
Wallace, O.P., “Nature and Human Nature as the Norm in Medical Ethics,” in Catholic
Perspectives on Medical Morals, eds. Edmund D. Pellegrino, John P. Langan, and
John Collins Harvey (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1989), 23–52.
38 William A.
Wallace, O.P., The Modeling of Nature: Philosophy of Science and Philosophy of
Nature in Synthesis (Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America
Press, 1996), 100–106.
39 “But an
animal is such primarily by sensation. For we also call animals things that do not
move or change their place, provided they have sensation, and do not merely
live. There seem to be many of this sort: by nature they stay in one place, but
they have one of the senses.” Aristotle, De Anima: Books II and III, 413
b2–4. St. Thomas in commenting on this passage of the Philosopher notes, “there
are many such animals whose nature restricts them to one place, but which have
the power of sense, e.g., shell-fish, which cannot move from place to place.” Commentary
on Aristotle’s “De Anima,” Lecture III, n. 259. Later on in this commentary,
St. Thomas makes the distinction that local motion is a characteristic only of
the higher animals: “For the present it suffices to say that soul is the
one principle underlying the four distinct modes in which life is manifested,
namely the vegetative mode which belongs to plants and to all living things;
the sensitive mode in all animals; the intellectual mode in all men; and
fourthly, the mode that is a power to move from place to place, which exists in
all the higher animals, both those with sense only and those with intellect as
well.” Commentary on Aristotle’s “De Anima,” Lecture III, n. 261.
All citations from St. Thomas’s commentary are taken from Thomas Aquinas, Commentary
on Aristotle’s “De Anima,” trans. Kenelm Foster, O.P., and Silvester
Humphries, O.P. (Notre Dame, IN: Dumb Ox Books, 1994).
40 See Ashley,
“A Critique,” 115–121, and Stephen J. Heaney, “Aquinas and the Presence of the
Human Rational Soul in the Early Embryo,” The Thomist 56 (1992): 19–48.
41 For a
detailed discussion of St. Thomas’ understanding of human generation, see Michael
Allyn Taylor, “Human Generation in the Thought of Thomas Aquinas: A Case Study on
the Role of Biological Fact in Theological Science,” (S.T.D. diss., The
Catholic University of America, 1982). Also of interest is the essay by Jacques
Maritain, “Toward a Thomist Idea of Evolution,” in Untrammeled Approaches
(The Collected Works of Jacques Maritain, Vol. 20), Jacques Maritain
and Bernard Doering (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1997),
85–131.
42 Ashley, “A
Critique,” 121.
43 Mammalian
embryos are characterized by conditional specification of the cells, in which
cell identity is determined primarily by the interactions among the cells
rather than by one cell or by a single group of cells. For details, see Scott
F. Gilbert, Developmental Biology, 6th ed. (Sunderland, MA: Sinauer
Associates, 2000), 56–66.
44 See Robert
Pasnau, Thomas Aquinas on Human Nature: A Philosophical Study of “Summa
Theologiae,” 1a, 75–89 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002),
103–104.
45 Porter, “Is
the Embryo a Person?” 10.
46 Significantly,
even the most ardent proponents of legalized abortion acknowledge that the
earliest human embryo is the same human organism as the adult. What they
dispute is the moral status; i.e., the personhood, of this human organism at
the earliest stages of its development. For example, see Mary Ann Warren, “On
the Moral and Legal Status of Abortion,” The Monist 57.1 (January 1973),
reprinted in Joel Feinberg, ed. The Problem of Abortion, 2nd ed.
(Belmont, CA: Wadsworth Publishing, 1984), 102–119.
47 I am indebted
to Larry Arnhart’s analysis for the ideas and references mentioned in this
paragraph. See his Darwinian Natural Right: The Biological Ethics of Human
Nature (Albany, NY: SUNY Press, 1998), 232–238.
48 Michael Ruse,
“Biological Species: Natural Kinds, Individuals, or What?” British Journal
for the Philosophy of Science 38 (1987): 225–242.
49 For details,
see Scott Atran, Cognitive Foundations of Natural History: Towards an Anthropology
of Science (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990), and Brent Berlin,
Ethnobiological Classification: Principles of Categorization of Plants and
Animals in Traditional Societies (Princeton: Princeton University Press,
1992).
A
Challenge Met
This paper
has responded to Porter’s challenge to Catholics to reconcile a theory of
immediate hominization with the philosophical principles that are rooted in their
own tradition, by advancing a philosophical framework that reformulates hylomorphic
theory in light of recent scientific discoveries. Especially significant, and
probably most controversial, is the proposal to combine the plant/animal
categories associated with classical hylomorphism. The human soul and every
other kind of soul would be understood here not according to their generic
powers but by their capacities to organize the molecular network that drives
species-specific development. It is a proposal that enhances the explanatory
power of hylomorphic theory without sacrificing its basic principles, which
affirm the substantiality of living organisms that are able to change and yet
remain the same. Not insignificantly, systems hylomorphism also justifies a
theory of immediate hominization that embraces the fully personal status of the
very early-stage human embryo.
Let me be the
first to acknowledge that much work remains to be done with the systems
perspective. The most important task ahead would be to develop the conceptual
framework so that it can explain how and if particular genetic mutations of
either natural or artificial origin can so affect the disposition of matter
that the organism that results has been changed enough so that it can be
considered a different species, a question that will shape the response of
Catholic bioethics to genetic engineering.50 This would involve computer modeling of dynamic
networks.51 However,
as the Angelic Doctor himself acknowledged by appropriating the methods of his
pagan predecessors and contemporaries, the Catholic intellectual tradition can and
should be advanced and made more intelligible to our contemporaries by
borrowing ideas and concepts from the secular sciences. Finally, the physical
and metaphysical framework of systems hylomorphism needs to be integrated with
a more personal and existential account of the human being. Only a holistic
view of this type would do justice to the embodied spiritual creature who is
the human person.
50 Recent popes
have suggested that nature should not be modified but “helped to develop.”
However, the line between modifying nature and favoring its development is not clear.
By distinguishing genetic modifications that give rise either to accidental or
to substantial changes, the systems perspective may be able to clarify this
distinction. For an ethical overview of issues raised by genetic engineering,
see my “Genetic Engineering, Post- Genomic Ethics, and the Catholic Tradition,”
National Catholic Bioethics Quarterly 1.4 (Winter 2001): 497–506.
51 Computer
modelling would allow one to compare different dynamic systems to each other
and to a species-specific standard. Thus, one would be able to determine if a
particular living system belongs to the species; i.e., does not differ from the
species-specific standard.
No comments:
Post a Comment