Perspectivism:
Aquinas and Nietzsche on Intellect and Will
Walter J. Thompson
1.
I
propose to examine here the riyal and often radically conflicting views of
Aquinas and Nietzsche on the role played by intellect and will in human
activity.1 As the problem occupies so
central a position in the thought of each – it is virtually the cornerstone of
their respective anthropologies – I will not dwell on justifying my choice of
theme. Still, if the topic itself seems unproblematic, perhaps the larger comparative
project does not. Some may doubt the very possibility of the sort of encounter
of rivals that I propose to facilitate. It might be objected, for example, that
the two riyal accounts are so radically conflicting as to be incommensurable,
that the antagonists share no common language in which to articulate their
problems in a mutually intelligible way, and therefore, that genuine dialogue
between them is impossible. If their accounts are indeed incommensurable, then
Aquinas and Nietzsche cannot be construed as speaking about, as offering riyal
accounts of, the same things. An encounter between such incommensurable views
will prove impossible because there will be no commonly acceptable criteria by
which to adjudicate their conflict. Indeed, it will be impossible even to identify
the problems at stake in a mutually acceptable way, since what counts as a
problem and why will itself vary across the riyal viewpoints. If this
incommensurability holds, how can the two thinkers be brought into
conversation?
To
these objections, I offer two responses. First and most obviously, while common
explanatory criteria may be unavailable in this case, there remains a deeper
commonality to which we may appeal. For it seems an ineliminable mark of all
accounts to intend to explain, to give a compelling account of the phenomena
they consider. However divergent the riyal ways in which such an intention may
be fulfilled, the deep intention to fulfill it remains common. It is this deep
intention which justifies our grouping together divergent views as rivals, as
contenders in a common enterprise. Despite the radical differences in their
accounts of intellect and will, both Aquinas and Nietzsche purport to be
offering an explanation of certain fundamental features of human experience.
However much their accounts finally diverge, they are united by this deep
intention.
Second,
as this study will attempt to show, it may be that the apparent
incommensurability between the two accounts is surmountable, if we can show
that the incommensurability itself is unidirectional. If, that is, one of the
two accounts can encompass its riyal, can provide an account that both saves
the successes and explains the failures of its rival successes and failures
intelligible to the riyal in its own terms then the problem of incommensurability
will be overcome from the perspective of the encompassing account.2 Such a conclusion, however, requires an
argument, which I will now attempt. I will examine the views of both Aquinas
and Nietzsche on the relation of intellect and will, expounding each view in
itself and then in confrontation with its riyal. Finally, I will attempt to
adjudicate the conclusion of that confrontation. Let us begin with the view
advanced by Aquinas.
2.
To
avoid possible misunderstandings, we would do well to begin by examining
Aquinas' order and manner of treatment. Looking to the Summa Theologiae,3 we notice that detailed analyses of intellect
and will occur in two contexts: first, in the prima pars, in the discussion of
the creation and distinction of things, where Aquinas proceeds along the
hierarchy of being that issues from God to arrive at human beings, there to
treat intellect and will as powers which belong to the nature of such beings;
second, in the prima secundae, in the discussion of those acts by which human
beings come to the perfection of their nature, where Aquinas treats the role
played by each of these powers in human action. Aquinas sets his treatment of
human psychology, then, within a larger account of the nature of human being in
particular, and of created being generally. In this treatment, moreover, he
employs explanatory principles which he takes to hold for being generally.
Those most commonly employed in the account of intellect and will are the
Aristotelian concepts of potency and act and of the “four causes.”4 We will examine the uses of each principle as
the occasion arises.
The
type of account Aquinas gives an explanatory account should also be
differentiated from an introspective or phenomenological description. For
Aquinas, description can provide materials for the construction of an
explanatory account, but description is not itself explanation. In his account
of intellect and will, Aquinas rarely appeals to introspective evidence largely,
it would seem, because it has little to offer in the way of explanation. He
does not allow the human soul intuitive or introspective self-knowledge.
Instead, he argues that the soul comes to know its own nature in the same way
that it comes to know the nature of other beings by constructing an explanation
that can account for the phenomena.5
In the case of the soul, the phenomena in question are the various actions
which it engages. As a potency, the soul must know itself as it knows all
potencies, by reflection on the acts proper to it.6
Let us turn, then, to Aquinas' two treatments of intellect and will: first, in
themselves, as powers of the rational soul within the structure of human being
considered statically; and second, in their relation within the dynamic structure
of human action.
For
Aquinas, intellect and will are powers or potencies proper to the rational
soul, the substantial form of the human being. Because the soul is a finite
created substance, its essence is not its perfect operation. Rather it is in
potentiality to diverse operations, and to each of these in diverse ways. The
powers of the soul are the principles of those operations by which the soul is
brought to its perfection in act.7
The
powers, then, are potencies directed to acts. As with all potencies, they are
diversified according to the nature of the act toward which they are directed;
and acts themselves are diversified according to the nature of their object.
Powers, then, are specified by their formal objects or, more precisely, by the
formality under which they are related to their objects.8 This distinction bears emphasis for, as we
shall later see, a thing one in reality may be regarded under various formal
aspects, and so be the object of various powers.9
Intellect
is that power of the soul which is in potency to knowing truth, or that power
by which the soul is related to being under the aspect or notion of the true.
Thus the proper object of the intellect is being qua intelligible. Will, on the
other hand, as a species of appetite, is that power of the soul which is in
potency to desiring or inclining to good, or that power by which the soul is
related to being under the aspect or notion of the good. Thus the proper object
of the will is being qua appetible. The powers of intellect and will, then, are
differentiated according to the formal aspect under which they are related to
their common object, being.
The
powers of the soul are potencies, Aquinas argues, and a potency must be moved
to act by something already in act. This cause of motion can be either a
principle, which moves as a moving mover, or an object, which moves as a term
or end. A power, therefore, can be in potency in two ways: first, with respect
to its operation – whether it be exercised or no – and second, with respect to
its object whether the end of its exercise be this or that. Both intellect and
will are passive with respect to both their operation and object. Each awaits a
cause for its exercise and for its determination.
It
belongs to the will, Aquinas argues, to move to exercise. Regarding operation
will can, as agent or efficient cause, move both itself and intellect to
exercise. This is so because under the will's proper object, the common notion
of the good, are subsumed all the particular goods which belong to particular
exercises of the powers.10 Will,
therefore, insofar as it intends a more universal end the good in general moves
the powers directed to more particular ends to their operation.11 It belongs to the intellect, on the other
hand, to move by determination. Intellect can, as end or formal cause, move
both itself and will to the specification of its act, by presenting a power
with its object. In this respect, under the proper object of intellect the
common notion of being and truth are subsumed all particular truths regarding
the powers and their proper acts and objects.12
The relation between will and intellect in general, then, is one of reciprocal
causality: will as efficient cause moves both itself and intellect to exercise,
intellect as formal cause moves both itself and will to determination. l3 The causality of the powers is not univocal,
but of diverse kinds. Will causes an operation to be, intellect causes it to be
such and so. The formal differentiation of the two powers is not a real separation,
rather, as Aquinas says, “these powers include one another in their acts. l4
Having
said this much, certain difficulties with Aquinas' account seem immediately to
arise. In the first place, how do we overcome what appears to be a vicious
circularity in the causality of intellect and will? How do we avoid an infinite
regress of causes if the exercise of a particular act of intellect depends on a
prior act of will, which in turn depends for its determination on a prior act
of intellect, which itself depends for its exercise on a prior act of will, and
so on? How do we overcome the problem that both intellect and will are in
potency with respect to both their exercise and their determination? If we
suppose that we must begin from an initial inertial state, and if we conceive
of causality solely in terms of mechanistic efficient causes, then the
circularity cannot be overcome. Aquinas himself, however, makes neither
supposition. Instead, he argues for the inherent natural dynamism of the
powers, the natural directedness of the powers toward their proper ends.15 The will, Aquinas argues, is by nature
inclined to the universal good, the intellect to the universal true. Pushing
the argument further, Aquinas claims that God himself, as first cause of the being
and final end of the operation of all natures, is the first cause of such
natural movements in things.l6 God is
the ultimate source of the natural inclinations of created beings; and beings
are created by God as naturally inclined, as naturally ordered to certain
operations and ends. Thus intellect naturally knows first common principles in
both speculative and practical matters, while will naturally wills the first
principle of voluntary movement, the universal good and last end, under which
is
subsumed all that
pertains to the wellbeing of the agent as a whole.17
Such universal motion to the end makes possible every particular act of will,
for it is the common notion under which any particular good is willed, the
efficient cause which moves every particular act of will. Yet while in the
absence of such universal motion, no particular good could be willed, it
remains for intellect to determine each particular act of will to this or that
particular apprehended good.
The
natural teleology of the powers, therefore, overcomes the problem of initial
inertia, while the problem of regress is overcome by the recognition that we
are dealing not with a temporal series of univocal efficient causes, but with
the operation of necessarily concomitant causes which differ in kind. Intellect
moves to determination, will to exercise; intellect acts as formal, will as agent
cause. The operation of each is necessary to any particular act.
A
second potential difficulty arises in attempting to sort out the problems of
agency that arise in any so-called “faculty psychology.” Aquinas himself treats
this problem in replying to an objection which argues that, since appetite is
naturally devoid of understanding, will can in no way receive and heed a
command of reason. Aquinas responds that the powers of the soul operate not for
themselves alone but for the whole human being. Thus any statement which
attributes agency to a power can be translated into one which speaks of the
human being who possesses such powers as the real agent.18 Faculties or powers, though they are to be
formally differentiated, cannot be really separated. They are not themselves
supposits spiritual organs, as it were but are potentialities which inhere in
integral human agents.
Having
examined intellect and will in themselves, as powers of the rational soul, let
us turn to a brief examination of the role each plays in two sorts of human
activity. I have in mind here Aquinas' distinction between speculative and
practical activity, a distinction grounded in his differentiation of two
corresponding sorts of intellect. Again, however, this analytic differentiation
does not amount to a real separation, for while the speculative and practical
intellects differ in their material object – the speculative concerned with
necessary intelligibles and the practical with contingent operables – still
they share a common formal object being under the aspect of the true.19 They differ again with respect to their end,
for the speculative intellect directs apprehension to the consideration of truth
alone, and its truth consists in the conformity of the intellect to its object;
the practical intellect, on the other hand, directs apprehension to operation,
and so its truth consists in the conformity of intellect with right appetite,
which in disposing to the right end disposes to right operation.20 This ordering of apprehension to a further
end, however, remains an accidental and not an essential distinction, and so
Aquinas admits only one power of intellect.21
These
two sorts of intellect are, however, diversely related to the will. Will does
not enter into the constitution of speculative reason's object, the necessary
true, while it does enter into the constitution of practical intellect's
object, a contingent operable.22 Let
us apply our previous conclusions on the relation of will and intellect
generally to these two cases. First, will can move both the speculative and the
practical intellect to its operation or exercise.23
While it cannot itself apprehend a thing as such and so, it can move intellect
to the act which culminates in such an apprehension, an apprehension which may
or may not then specify a further act of will. Thus will can, if indirectly,
contribute to its own determination, by causing the exercise of that act of intellect
which may subsequently determine it. Second, in speculative matters, will
cannot determine intellect's object, for that object is something that cannot
be other, something whose intelligibility cannot be altered by willing it so.
In practical matters, on the other hand, will enters into the very constitution
of intellect's object. The object of practical intellect is a possible thing to
be done. Possible things to be done are judged by practical intellect according
to their goodness or appropriateness. Goodness, however, is the proper object
of the will, and the good is that which is desirable. Fully to know a thing as
good, then, is to know it as desirable, and therefore as something toward which
the will is inclined. The disposition of the will toward a possible thing to be
done serves to mark it as a thing good and to be done or evil and to be
avoided.24
To
recapitulate, the operation of will is necessary to make use of the power of
intellect, both speculative and practical, in allowing or bringing about
intellect's relation to its object, while it serves to constitute the object
itself only of practical intellect. Such acts of use, as particular acts, must
exhibit the reciprocal causality of intellect and will, intellect moving to
determination, will to operation. And these acts of the component powers must
themselves be particular acts, that is, must themselves exhibit the mutual
causality of intellect and will the act of will specified by an act of
intellect, and the act of intellect moved by an act of will. Thus will's
causing the exercise of any particular act of intellect is not a moving to
exercise generally, but a particular choosing in some here and now to move the
power to operation. Moreover, choosing to exercise either the speculative or
the practical intellect is itself a matter of practice, of something to be
done, and therefore depends decisively on will's disposition toward that
exercise, as on practical intellect's apprehension and judgment. Both
speculative and practical activity, then, fall within the larger unity of
voluntary activity in general, of activity that proceeds from a deliberate
will. For such activity to be good activity, the proper disposition of both
intellect and will is required.
3.
Let
us turn next to Nietzsche. I will here construct a Nietzschean response to
Aquinas' account, setting forth Nietzsche's own riyal account only to the
extent necessary to construct this response. A fuller elaboration of the
Nietzschean alternative will follow later in the argument.
To
present Nietzsche's interpretation of Aquinas we must first know what it is on
Nietzsche's account to interpret, what on Nietzsche's view it means to forward
a view. For according to Nietzsche, views do not simply wear their meanings on
their sleeves, they are not transparent to their deeper significances. So,
confronting Aquinas, Nietzsche will ask: this Latin psychologist, what does he
really want, what is it that drives him in such a direction?25 To move toward a response to this Nietzschean
question we must first examine Nietzsche's teaching on perspective.
For
Nietzsche, all views without exception are perspective views, are
interpretations. Interpretations, moreover, are forwarded by determinate
character types, who fashion them in light of valuations relative to their
type. All interpretations both reflect and at the same time conceal an
interest.26 They are fundamentally
masks worn by a will to power which engenders them. To understand a view,
therefore, we must disclose the interest it conceals, and trace that interest
to the character type from which it proceeds. It is the Nietzschean
genealogist's task to unearth and evaluate what lies hidden behind and beneath
the surface ciphers of a view, to lay bare the character of that constellation
of motives which gives rise to it. The truly decisive question regarding any
view, therefore, is not “what is it?” but “from whom is it?”that is, what
character type does such a view serve and how, or more precisely, what is the
character of the will to power manifest in such a view.27 Thus the content of a view becomes a symptom
of a state of forces, a cipher of a character.28
The interpretation of a view becomes the evaluation of one type of character
(and its masks) by another.
Let
us turn then to Aquinas' view, looking to what he does as a clue to what
character type he is. What Aquinas does is to forward a certain kind of
account, a philosophic account, which offers an explanation of intellect and
will in the context of a broader account of nature or being. Such an account
treats human nature and human psychology on the basis of principles of
explanation taken to hold for being generally, principles at least potentially
accessible to those with adequate aptitude in the use of reason. Such a
totalizing view, Nietzsche argues, in forwarding the myth of an “order of
things” accessible to the rational, denies the creative and perspectival
character of interpretation. It denies differences in type, subjecting all
alike to the tyranny of the same rational order. On Nietzsche's account, such a
view is but a mask that conceals the working of a will to power of a certain
type a type that feels the need to deny what differs from itself through
totalizing claims; a type that, feeling itself subject, would reduce all to a
similar subjection. Such a type is weak and base, and such a view is but an
elaborate rationalization and projection on a cosmic scale of that peculiar
mode of being. The action of this type is a reaction: too weak to affirm its
own difference, it denies the difference of others.
The
Thomistic account which vindicates this type, which fashions an order within
which it might feel at home, is according to Nietzsche but a scholarly version
of the morality of the weak and base all the more contemptible perhaps for its
perverse ingenuity.29 In forwarding
such a supposedly universal account, Aquinas is in fact playing the duplicitous
advocate, taking refuge in the fiction of an “order of things” because he lacks
both the strength of character to self-consciously assume the authorship of his
own interpretations, and the nobility of spirit to affirm himself in affirming
the perspectival character of his views.30
Aquinas'
treatment of human psychology and human action views human acts as those which
proceed from a deliberate will, and so those over which we are master. On a
Nietzschean reading such a separation of doer and deed denies the efficacy of
will to power, again for a reason which serves the interest of the weak. It
sets over the expression of a type's force, its character, a neutral substratum
which it falsely supposes is free and because free responsible to express its
inherent character or not, to discharge its force or not. Such a view is the
self=deception of impotence which masks the necessity of will to power's
causality with the illusion of free conscious agency. “The subject,” says
Nietzsche, “(or to use a more popular expression, the soul), makes possible to
the majority of mortals, the weak and oppressed of every kind, the sublime self-deception
that interprets weakness as freedom, and their being thus and thus as a merit.”31 The weak and base, who are constitutionally
incapable of true action that is, of self affirmation interpret the necessary
expression of their impotence as praiseworthy self-restraint, and likewise
condemn the strong for choosing to give vent to the seeming excess which is but
the necessary expression of their type.32
In either case, a fictitious agent is held to be responsible for what in truth
cannot be other.
Aquinas
further treats human powers and operations in terms of a natural teleology in
which each power is ordered to some end proper to it, the realization or
attainment of which constitutes that power's proper perfection. That
perfection, moreover, then provides a measure by which to evaluate the success
or failure of any particular operation of that power. On a Nietzschean view,
such an elaborate teleological scheme denies the universal efficacy of will to
power, substituting instead a multitude of superfluous principles.33 It denies the multiplicity of evaluative
principles which arise from differences in type, differences in the character
of will to power manifest in a given type. In short, it denies the interested
character of evaluation and substitutes a monolithic measure of adequacy taken
to be binding on all perspectives.
4.
In
laying out this Nietzschean critique of Aquinas' position, I wonder if I have
not said far too much, if I have not quite naively acted the philosopher in
attempting to apply Nietzsche's principles to the Thomistic account. For
fundamental to Nietzsche's position would seem to be a self-conscious refusal
to play the philosopher's game, to suppose that what we are about here is
argument, debate, the reasoned consideration of alternatives. Perhaps the most
consistently Nietzschean response to the Thomistic account would be no response
at all. The self-conscious Nietzschean would not be interested in joining the
issue with his riyal, indeed, would not acknowledge any issue between them. The
Nietzschean strong and noble type needs no, and so seeks no, justification of
his own view. Unlike the weak he does not need to vindicate
himself through
comparison. Indeed, the very notion of vindication is radically alien to the
character of the one who instinctively affirms his own difference, whose action
is a positing of self and not merely a denial of what is other.34 At best such a one would disdain what is
other than his type when he happens upon it, but he would certainly feel no
need to seek it out in order to prove a superiority he affirms from the start.
The
authentic Nietzschean, therefore, would be little interested in engaging in the
sort of dialectical exchange into which I have cast him. Indeed, it would be
the death of his position to do so. That very few Nietzscheans – Nietzsche
himself included – find themselves able consistently to exercise such restraint
is a telling fact that we shall examine later at greater length. For now, let
us simply note the tension, and move on to an examination of Nietzsche's own
positive account of intellect and will.
5.
We
notice at the outset a pervasive duality of aspect in Nietzsche's treatment of
intellect and will. He examines each by turns from the standpoint of cosmology the
view on nature and from the standpoint of psychology the view from the subject.
Inquiring into the relation of these two views leads us immediately into
irresolvable problems of circularity. On the one hand, Nietzsche will have his
cosmological account ground the psychological, will have his teaching on nature
ground his teaching on perspective; on the other hand, and simultaneously, his
perspectivism requires that his cosmological account be given an explanation in
terms of perspective psychology. To sharpen the issue, the necessity for Nietzsche
to maintain the perspectival character of his teaching on perspective threatens
to impale him on the horns of self-referential absurdity.
Later
Nietzsche scholarship has recognized the peril of this duality of aspect and
has attempted to avert it by emphasizing one side of the teaching to the
neglect of the other.35 Such a neat
resolution, however, cannot suffice, for each aspect of Nietzsche's teaching
not only accidentally but essentially implies the other. The consistent
Nietzschean, moreover, must abjure any such tidy rational resolution.36 We will return to these problems
subsequently, when we have a firmer grasp on the particulars of Nietzsche's
account.
Let
us first consider the cosmological dimension. For Nietzsche all phenomena
whatever are expressions of force, or more precisely, of a constellation of
interacting forces.37 What a thing is
its essence is just this dynamic constellation of force. A thing is its
expression; it is its effect. The world is the larger field of force which
encompasses these component clusters in their dynamic relations, it is the
effect of the summation of effects. On a cosmic scale life is the play of these
contending forces and such play has the character of a struggle for mastery.
This play of life Nietzsche calls will to power. “A living thing seeks above
all to discharge its strength,” he says.38
And the world of such things is governed by “the tyrannically inconsiderate and
relentless enforcement of claims of power... and every power draws its ultimate
consequences at every moment.”39
Nietzsche,
then, posits will to power as the pervasive cause of all phenomena:
The question is in the end whether we
really recognize the will as efficient, whether we believe in the causality of
the will: if we do and at bottom our faith in this is nothing less than our
faith in causality itself then we have to make the experiment of positing the
causality of the will hypothetically as the only one... [Should one do so] then
one would have gained the right to determine all efficient force univocally as will
to power. The world viewed from inside, the world defined and determined
according to its “intelligible character “it would be “will to power” and
nothing else.40
While
thus maintaining the ubiquity of will to power's causality, Nietzsche does not
wish to deny, but rather to affirm the radical plurality of appearances, the
heterogeneity of phenomenal manifestations. The monism of will to power is
compatible with indeed is identical to the pluralism of its expression. It is
will to power that manifests itself in any thing's expression, in its force. It
is will to power that gives rise to, that differentiates, that relates the
order of forces which are the being of any thing.41
Thus will to power confers on any thing its peculiar character and makes it to
be of a certain type.
On
the cosmic level Nietzsche envisages two antinomic types of force and will: an
active force driven by a will which is affirmative; and a reactive force driven
by a will which is negative. In their manifestation in human beings these types
appear as the strong and noble as opposed to the weak and base human type.
Despite these divergences in types of manifestation, behind all manifestations
of force lies will to power. As Gilles Deleuze has written, for Nietzsche, “everywhere
and always the will to power is 'the one that.”42
Let
us turn next from the cosmological aspect of Nietzsche's teaching to the
psychological, from will to power's working in the world to its working in
human beings. We have seen above that will to power gives rise to,
differentiates, and orders expressions of force into types. In the phenomena we
call human beings such determinations specify distinct types of character. What
sets one human being apart from another is the character of force and its
directive will that that person manifests or more precisely, of which that
person's expression is the expression. If a human being, like all beings, is a
constellation of will driven force, and if the essence of force is its effect,
then a human being is the sum total of his effects, of those manifestations of
force we call actions or operations.43
Conversely, what a human being effects in any given situation will be the
necessary consequence of the type of his being, of the will driven force manifest
in him.44
Thus
for Nietzsche all the manifold activities in which human beings engage are the
many masks assumed by a will to power. Their deep significance is always to be
found in the character of will driven force manifest in them. All activities
proceed from, or are expressions of, distinct human types, and such types
differ radically. Still, all activities proceed toward an end which, while
varying materially by type and circumstance remains formally constant across
both type and circumstance namely, the advancement of the life of the actor,
the increase of his power.45
Thus
while the particular ways in which individuals further their existence may vary
radically across types, it remains the case that all individuals whatever their
type seek a formally common end. Similarly, while the particular means through
which a type furthers its existence may vary immensely, Nietzsche envisages but
two formal possibilities, which correspond to his basic distinction in types of
force and will. Strong and noble types further their lives through action through
the affirmation of their difference while weak and base types further their
lives through reaction through the denial of what differs. Now, as all
particular human acts are acts of particular human beings, and all particular
human beings are of a type, all human acts must issue from a determinate type.
Therefore all human acts will be driven by a will to power which seeks to
further a determinate mode of existence. What we say of any particular human
act, then, we must say in reference to the needs of a determinate type, the
demands of a determinate life.46
If
it is true that each thing qua living seeks to further its life, and qua type
seeks to further its determinate way of life, it is also true that the operations
by or in which a thing pursues its goal vary according to the kind of thing it
is. Thus all that live share a common end, all of a type share a common
character, and all of a kind share common functions or operations. As all
particular instances of a kind are of a determinate type, particular exercises
of a function must themselves be in the service of determinate types serving
their lives through them. Functions, therefore, or their uses, must also be
differentiated by type, according to the character of will-driven force they
serve and express.
In
exploring human beings, then, we must look to them first as a kind sharing
common functions, and next as types possessing distinct characters. Among the
several functions common to human beings we will concern ourselves here with
intellect and will alone, looking to each in itself and to both in relation,
first as to their common function and second as to their determinate uses.
For
Nietzsche, intellect as a function is not fundamentally a cognitive or contemplative
power, but an interpretive or creative one. In an earlier context we adverted
to Nietzsche's teaching that all views are perspectival interpretations. Let us
here elaborate. Interpretation is for Nietzsche a matter more of eisegesis than
of exegesis: it confers, it does not discover meaning. Through intellect a
determinate character fashions for itself a meaningful world in which its type
can feel at home.47 Such creation or
conferral of meaning is perspectival, that is, relative to a type, and so is
driven by that will to power of which the type is the manifestation.
Intellect, then, is
an instrument in the hands of will to power, and its products interpretations are
a means through which will to power works its way in human being.48 Perhaps, however, the language of
instrumentality misleads by reifying and separating the function and its ruling
will, whereas for Nietzsche particular exercises of a function are not
accidentally or extrinsically but essentially or intrinsically related to will
to power. He call that on his view the essence of a thing is its effect, the
expression of its inherent force, and will to power both gives rise to and
gives order to such an expression. In human beings such force is expressed
through the operation of those functions peculiar to their kind. Such
operations, then, belong neither to faculties nor agents, but are simply the
expression of that will-driven force which is the being of the human being.
Let
us now turn from intellect as a function common to the kind of thing we call a
human being, to its particular uses in diverse character-types. Nietzsche
differentiates particular uses of intellect according to the second order
attitude which diverse types assume toward the nature of intellect as a
function. Here as always for Nietzsche, as the type is, so is the act; and as
the will is, so is the type. To diverse types of will to power, therefore,
correspond diverse types of exercise of what on the surface appears to be a
common function. Operations diverge in character as radically as the character types
from which they proceed, and for the same reason. Let us look to these
divergences.
It
is the mark of the weak and base, Nietzsche holds, to mask the creative
function of intellect, to deny its interpretive and perspectival character, and
to substitute a totalizing interpretation of its role which masquerades as the
truth of things. Too weak to self-consciously assume the awful necessity of
truth-creation, the weak and base deny it, taking refuge in the fiction of a
real order of things accessible to and binding on all. Lacking the nobility of
spirit necessary to affirm themselves in affirming their own interpretations as
interpretive, in donning their masks self-consciously, they end by denying
interpretation altogether, and subjecting all to their unacknowledged
creations.
The
strong and noble, on the other hand, because their action is an affirmation of
their own difference, self-consciously affirm the creative function of
intellect. Because they glory in themselves, they glory too in their self-expression.
They own their interpretations as interpretive, as perspectival. They know
their knowing to be a free creation proceeding from a will to power which makes
them to be what they are. Such types renounce the petty comfort of subjection
to any totalizing view and assume the terrible but liberating responsibility of
truth-creation. Unlike the weak, they need not hide the interested origins of
their views from themselves at any rate but don their masks self-consciously,
in full recognition of their perspectival character. Only in this way is their
exercise of intellect an affirmation of difference, only so does their
operation conform to their character, to the type of will to power manifest in
them.
Turning
now from intellect to will, we first note that willing as an operation of the
kind of being we call human is not for Nietzsche equivalent to will to power.
Rather, as with all functions, acts of will are surface expressions or
manifestations of a deeper force-will to power. What we call willing is but a
channel through which, or a means by which, this more fundamental drive is
vented. As expressions of will to power, therefore, particular will-acts
receive their meaning from the character of that which they express, from the
type of will to power they display.
As
an operation, Nietzsche sees willing as “above all something complicated,
something that is a unit only as a word.49
He offers us this phenomenological description:
[T]he will is not only a complex of
sensation and thinking, but it is above all an affect, and specifically the
affect of the command.... A man who wills commands something within himself
that renders obedience, or that he believes renders obedience.50
Coincident
in any instance of willing, then, are a manifold of volitional sensations, a
ruling thought, and the simultaneous affects of command and obedience. These
exist in an inseparable complex. Their mutual relation and not any one taken in
isolation constitutes the phenomenon we call willing. This complex, moreover,
is not an act effected by some agent, but a manifold acted within an agent by
will to power. It is will to power and not some sovereign subject that wills in
our willing.51 The fiction of the
sovereign subject is the interpretation of a certain type, the weak and base,
who separate agent and act, force and effect, that they might view as voluntary
and so meritorious what is but the necessary expression of their innermost
character.52 The strong and noble, on
the other hand, recognize that behind or beneath their willing is no free and
independent subject, but the necessity of will to power. They admit that the
very force of their character compels them to discharge their inherent power,
to express their strength.53 The
weak, while equally bound to this necessity of character, mask it by means of
the fiction of moral agency, of freedom of will. And they do so in order that
they, who are too weak to enjoy the pleasure of commanding and subduing others
through an affirmation of self, might feel the vicarious pleasure of mastery
over self through a denial of strength, and so suppose their impotence an achievement.
Regarding
the relation of intellect and will as functions, Nietzsche sees the operations
of intellect and will as inextricably intertwined. In any human act we will
find an inseparable complex of thought directed will and will prompted thought.54 The exercise of neither, it would seem, can
exist in isolation. There can be no thinking without willing, no willing
without thinking.55 Their differentiation
as functions, moreover, masks a deeper unity, for the operation of both is
fundamentally an expression of will to power. A will to power of a certain type
always lies behind each instance of thinking willing, giving rise to it, giving
meaning to it, giving value to it.56
Finally,
let us consider the attitude assumed by the divergent types of human being
toward the relation of intellect and will to one another and to will to power.
It is characteristic of the weak and base, Nietzsche maintains, to mask the causality
of will to power through the reification of functions into independent faculties
whose operation is subject to the control of a neutral subject. The strong and
noble, on the other hand, self-consciously affirm both the inseparability of thinking-willing,
and the dependence of this complex on a will to power of a certain type. In
short, each type responds to the relation of the functions in a way congruent
with its own mode of being, in a way that furthers its own life.
6.
Having
set forth the Nietzschean counter-position, I will now attempt to construct a
Thomistic response. At the outset we should note that a Thomistic critique will
differ from a Nietzschean in this, that while by the internal logic of his own
position the Nietzschean cannot engage in dialectic cannot enter into an
argument without subjecting himself to the terms of his rival, and therefore
without renouncing his position on perspective the Thomistic critique must be dialectical
in form, must join the issue on the interlocutor's own ground and attempt to
show him on his own terms the impossibility of maintaining his position. Such a
dialectical critique must, moreover, provide an account that can explain that
impossibility. My own critique will focus on what I take to be the cornerstone
of Nietzsche's account, his teaching on perspective. But first, let us address
some points of detail.
A
Thomist will wonder, first, how Nietzsche can deny the existence of a subject
of activity, of an agent independent of its acts, by asserting that a thing is
but the sum of its effects. How, the Thomist will ask, can we speak of a sum
without presupposing something to which the things summed accrue? Nietzsche may
protest that it is only grammatical habit that compels us to speak in this way,57 but the Thomist will respond that it is a
telling fact that we cannot speak otherwise, that our thought, and so our
language, will allow us no alternative. And for one who finds an essential
connection between our mode of knowing and speaking and our mode of being, the
mute dismissal of grammatical habit seems cavalier.
Second,
regarding Nietzsche's understanding of will to power's universal efficacy, the
Thomist will ask: if will to power is always “the one that,” and if its
expression cannot be other, why are Nietzsche's pages filled with exhortation,
with denunciation, with exultation, with lament? Why quarrel with necessity?
Why not rather resign oneself to the inevitable?58
Nietzsche's own practices threaten to give the lie to his account.
Third,
with respect to Nietzsche's account of the best type of human life, the Thomist
will wonder just what it is that makes such a life best. The strong and noble
type, we recall, is the one who creates meaning, purpose, and direction, who,
in Nietzsche's words, “overcomes.” The context within which Nietzsche offers
such a teaching on the best sort of human life is a genealogical unmasking of
common morality and its claim to be grounded in the “nature of things.”
Nietzsche appears to deny the existence of any such natural order and to ground
his own rival account in the impossibility of discovering any such norm. Yet
here the Thomist will wonder whether, despite his intentions, Nietzsche is not
himself forwarding an account of the “nature of things” as norm.
Nietzsche replaces a
purposive teleological natural order, conformity to which constitutes human
perfection, with an alternative vision of a nature without purpose or direction
which, he claims, can function as no norm. If purpose or value is to exist, he
argues, it must be created by man or, more precisely, by a certain type of man.
Such a type is “the one who overcomes,” the one who freely and self-consciously
posits from his own way of being meaning, value, and purpose. It is significant
that Nietzsche forwards his account of such a type within the context of a
broader account of nature, that he does feel the need to debunk the traditional
account and to provide a riyal account in which his ideal type seems more at
home. In this sense, Nietzsche does not wish his ideal human type to be a mere
rebel against the order of things. What, then, is the true extent of the
freedom of “the one who overcomes”?
He
is not, it would seem, utterly or indiscriminately free. Indeed, he is in a
certain sense bound by at least the formal criterion that, whatever else he may
be, he must be one who overcomes, one who creates meaning, purpose, and value.
This criterion, then, “the one who overcomes” is not free to create. Though Nietzsche
refuses to specify the determinate forms that overcoming may assume, he does
bind his ideal type to this formal requirement. The freedom of such a type is
not absolute, but conditioned. His is an ordered freedom, a freedom to – in
this case, to overcome. In fact, his freedom is a form of enslavement –
enslavement to the necessity of life as will to power. 59
Given
this fact, the question immediately arises: why is freedom understood in such a
way normative? What distinguishes this from all other norms which Nietzsche has
with such vehemence debunked? In response, Nietzsche seems to argue that he who
overcomes is true to life, that life is will to power, and that the character
of will to power is overcoming. But again we must ask, why then is life as will
to power normative? Isn't Nietzsche here doing precisely that for which he
denounces all previous philosophers, namely, forwarding a teaching on the “nature
of things,” conformity to which constitutes the best type of human life?
Despite his vigorous protests to the contrary, isn't he arguing that nature or
the order of things is such and so, therefore human activity should be such and
so, that is, in conformity with the “nature of things?”60 If Nietzsche is in fact offering such an
account, then it remains difficult for a Thomist to see how he can continue to
exempt himself from the requirement of justifying his account as an account. If
he can no longer claim to be engaged in an enterprise radically different from
that of past philosophers, can he maintain the privilege of placing his account
above dialectical scrutiny?
For
our fourth point, let us examine the relation of Nietzsche as author to the
account he authors. Let us compare what Nietzsche is doing in giving an account
with the content of the account he gives.
Nietzsche,
we will argue, betrays more of the tacit Thomist in himself than he would care
to admit. Given his teaching on perspective and the relation of perspectives to
determinate types of will to power, why is it that Nietzsche feels the need to
communicate his discovery to us, to invite us to consider his view? Why does he
forward his account in opposition to riyal accounts? Now, he may respond that
his doing so is but a form of self-affirmation, but it remains striking that
his affirmations take this form. Given what Nietzsche has said of the strong
and noble type, the last thing we would expect from him would be the deliberate
and detailed exposition of the opposition of the strong and noble and the weak
and base human types. Indeed, the very mark of the strong and noble type as Nietzsche
understands him is a terrible yet carefree indifference to all forms of
selfjustification.61 His self is its
own justification; he need enter no comparison to be vindicated. The need to
vindicate oneself through comparison is precisely the province of the weak and base,
whose impotence compels them to give an account.
It
remains difficult to see how Nietzsche can escape this difficulty. His own
activity as author contradicts the teaching he authors; his deeds give the lie
to his words. Nietzsche attempts to vindicate his view in the face of its
rivals, while forwarding a view that maintains both the impossibility of
meaningful vindication and the superiority of that view which recognizes the
impossibility and renounces the quest for vindication. It may be objected that Nietzsche
is here offering no vindication but an interpretation, one affected in full
knowledge of its perspectival character. Such a retort, however, misses the
fundamental point. It is not what is offered, but the fact of the offering that
is decisive. Nietzsche can take refuge behind the play of words, but he cannot
hide the fact of his speaking. Such speaking betrays a deep need to justify, to
give an account of one's views. And this in turn manifests a still more
fundamental desire, the desire to be right, to hold not just any view but a
true one.62 Nietzsche's own deeds in
this case bear witness to Aristotle's observation that all human beings by
nature desire to know. And is it perhaps a corollary of this desire that all
human beings wish the object of their desire to receive its due, that truth be
known for what it is and not otherwise? How else can we explain the natural
human inclination to argue, to offer accounts which intend to be true and to
resist those that appear to be false? Does not this reaction and it appears to
be Nietzsche's give the lie to Nietzsche's own account? Does it not imply that
we do pursue truth precisely as common, that the notion of the universality of
truth is inherent in our desire for it?
Now,
to maintain that truth is common is by no means to imply that it is equally
apparent to all. From the view that truth is common “in itself' does not follow
that it is common “to or for us.” To speak in Thomistic terms, though the order
of being the mind's grasp of which constitutes truth itself is common to all,
the apprehension of that order need not be. Indeed, given the palpable
diversity among potential knowers with respect to intelligence, interest,
character, and leisure, we have every reason to believe that it will not be.
Here the views of Aquinas and Nietzsche diverge radically, for while Aquinas
differentiates speaking of things “in themselves” from things “to or for us,”
differentiates the “order of being” from the “order of apprehension,” and
relates them as measure to potentially measured, Nietzsche seems to eliminate
the distinction altogether. There is no difference, he will argue, between
appearance and reality, between things for us and things in themselves. The
notion of a “real world” underlying the world of appearance is a fiction and no
innocent one at that, for it is fabricated by base, reactive types too weak to
assume the responsibility of perspectival truth creation.
To
put the issue between them succinctly, I would argue that Aquinas is in fact
the perspectivist, while Nietzsche, despite his protests, succumbs precisely to
a form of totalism. It is Aquinas who maintains that, while the order of being
is given prior to and as the condition of understanding, coming to know it is a
process whose success or failure depends decisively on the disposition of the
inquirer, on his perspective. Nietzsche, on the other hand, maintains that
there is no common reality intended by inquiry, that all knowing, whatever the
perspective of the knower, is truth creation.
For
Aquinas, one can choose in particular situations whether or not to attempt to
come to know. Through a particular act of will one can choose to inquire, to
exercise his intellective capacities, whether in things to be done, or in
things to be known alone. On a Thomistic account coming to know is a complex
process into which figure the dispositions not only of will and intellect our
focus here but of the passions, the senses, the body in short, of the whole
human being. Knowing is in this sense a process in which a concrete human agent
comes into relation to some particular intelligible object. Knowing is
perspectival in the sense that all potential knowers are particular agents
disposed in particular ways to particular objects, while all occasions for knowing
are themselves particular situations with determinate features which may
facilitate or hinder the process. Yet while all knowing is from embedded in and
conditioned by a determinate perspective, still it is too directed toward a
reality whose existence is given prior to its being known. The real “in itself'
becomes the real “to or for us” in and through an act of knowing which effects
a relation between a concrete human agent and some knowable object. In
attempting to give an account of this relation, any but realist presuppositions
would seem to lead us into irremediable difficulties, for any denial that it is
the real itself that is disclosed to us in this relation must marshal as
evidence some contrary insight, which must itself claim to be founded on an
adequate grasp of the real.
Nietzsche's
counter position takes the form of the quite radical and totalizing claim that
all knowing is not merely mediated or conditioned by the perspective of the
knower, but that the knower himself constructs an intelligible world out of the
resources of, and in harmony with, the needs of his own character. Such an
account of knowing holds for all perspectives. Types differ only in the
attitude they assume toward it, the strong affirming and the weak denying it.
If this is Nietzsche's position, it remains difficult to see how he can forward
it and avoid self-refutation. And it remains difficult to see why Nietzsche
would be speaking at all if not to forward it. If giving an account is not what
Nietzsche wishes to be up to, then maintaining silence would seem to be the
most appropriate response. Nietzsche, however, seems emphatically incapable of
silence, and given the fact of his speaking, we have every right to assume that
he wishes to submit himself to the requirements of conversation, chief among
which is the demand that in speaking one actually be saying something, be
making a claim, and therefore be excluding from one's claim all that one might
have said but did not. Now Nietzsche's claim is a universal one: that all knowing
is conscious or unconscious truth creation. As universal, it must apply also perhaps
especially to itself. And when applied to itself, it explodes the very claim it
purports to make.
At
this point, if the Nietzschean takes refuge in the excuse that he is not
engaging in argument, that he is not playing the philosopher's game, and so
need not subject himself to the conditions of argument, the conversation must
end. For time being short, and” the way of inquiry long, the Thomist cannot
squander his energies. And arguing with one who rejects the possibility of
argument is futile. The Nietzschean may find the Thomist's seriousness in this
regard amusing, but the Thomist is enough a Platonist to recognize that the
opposite of seriousness is not play but frivolity. And for the Thomist, to
press the issue beyond this point would be frivolous.
7.
To
conclude, let us return to what is fundamental in the disagreement between
Aquinas and Nietzsche. At issue are radically divergent views of the proper way
to philosophize, and to approach the history of philosophizing. Nietzsche's
genealogical method proceeds not through argument but through interpretation
and evaluation. It determines the meaning of a view by revealing its origin in
a will to power of a certain type. It then evaluates that view and that will
from without, from the perspective of the interpreter. It cannot enter into
debate with a rival, cannot criticize an opponent's view from within and show
it to be internally incoherent, but must attack from the outside. Genealogy,
then, consists in external total critique, in the confrontation of antinomic
perspectives. Aquinas' method, on the other hand, is dialectical, it attempts
to join an issue from within, on an interlocutor's own ground, and to show in
terms intelligible to that interlocutor the impossibility of maintaining his
position.
I
have attempted to show that Nietzsche's own account cannot explain the fact of
his giving it. Paradoxically, it is Aquinas who is able to explain what Nietzsche
is doing, and furthermore, to explain why Nietzsche's own account is unable to
do so. To the extent that Aquinas provides an explanation for Nietzsche's
failures, his account has vindicated itself at the bar of its rival. To say
this, however, in no way implies that the argument between them is closed, for
at least two reasons. First and most obviously, our analysis here was limited
to only one aspect of the thought of each. Many important issues remain to be
joined. Second, and more importantly, the encounter of rivals itself has proved
to be a fruitful tool of interpretation. The confrontation with an alien view
brings to light aspects of a teaching that would otherwise remain hidden in
this case, the latent perspectivism in Aquinas' teaching. Dialogic encounter,
then, aids us in getting to the bottom of a teaching and, through it, to the
real problems that teaching addresses. For these reasons, the analysis offered
here can be but a first step in a continuing project.
1. The author wishes to thank Edward A.
Goerner, Alasdair MacIntyre, John Roos, and Michael M. Waldstein for helpful
comments on an earlier draft. Research on this paper was supported by the
Earhart Foundation and the Department of Government and International Studies
at the University of Notre Dame.
2. This framing of the problem owes much
to Alasdair MacIntyre, 'The Relationship of Philosophy to Its Past,” in
Philosophy in History: Essays on the Historiography of Philosophy, Richard
Rorty, J. B. Schneewind and Quentin Skinner, eds. (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1984), 31-48.
3. I shall confine my analysis to this
text, for it provides in compact form the crux of the Thomistic position. A
complete account of Aquinas' teaching would need to consider the full range of
his writings on the subject, especially De Malo and the Quaestiones Disputate
De Anima. My own research into these texts suggests that they serve in diverse
ways to extend, but in no way to fundamentally alter, the analysis offered in
the Summa Theologiae. For an analysis of these texts which supports this view,
see Mark D. Jordan, 'The Transcendentality of Goodness and the Human Will,” in
Being and Goodness, Scott MacDonald, ed. (Ithaca and London: Cornell University
Press, 1991), 12950.
4. See Alan Donagan, “Thomas Aquinas on Human
Action,” in The Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy, Norman
Kretzmann, Anthony Kenny, and Jan Pinborg, eds. (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1982), 642.
5. For an elaboration, see George P.
Klubertanz, S.J., “The Unity of Human Activity,” The Modern Schoolman 27
(January 1950): 9196; and Jordan, “The Transcendentality of Goodness and the
Human Will,” 13435.
6. Summa Theologiae 1.87.3 (Hereafter, ST
part. question. article. (and, if necessary) reply to objection. Citations will
be to the Leonine text as found in the B. A. C. edition: (Madrid: Biblioteca de
Autores Cristianos, 1961). For further analysis, see Mark D. Jordan, Ordering
Wisdom: The Hierarchy of Philosophical Discourses in Aquinas (Notre Dame:
University of Notre Dame Press, 1986), Sec. 4.2: ''The Soul's Knowledge of
Itself.”
7. ST 1.77.1.
8. ST 1.77.3.
9. ST 1.80.1.2.
10. ST 1.82.4.
11. ST 12.9.1.
12. ST 12.9.1.
13. ST 12.9.1.3.
14. ST 1.82.4.1.
15. See Eleonore Stump, “Intellect, Will,
and the Principle of Alternate Possibilities,” in Christian Theism and the
Problems of Philosophy, Michael D. Beaty, ed. (Notre Dame and London:
University of Notre Dame Press, 1990), 266.
16. Compare ST 12.9.6; 1.105.5; and
1.105.5.3. See Jordan “The Transcendentality of Goodness and the Human Will,”
13840. On the relation of divine and human causality see the seminal work of
Bernard Lonergan, “St. Thomas' Theory of Operation.” Theological Studies 3
(1942): 390 et passim.
17. ST 12.10.1.
18. ST 12.17.5.2. See Donagan, 'Thomas
Aquinas on Human Action,” 654.
19. ST 1.79.9.3.
20. ST 12.57.5.3.
21. ST 1.79.11.
22. ST 12.57.5.3.
23. ST 12.17.6. For an explicit reference
to will's moving the speculative intellect to exercise, see ST 12.16.1.3.
24. This decisive point is not recognized
by commentators who excessively dichotomize intellective and volitional
functions. See, for example, Stump, “Intellect, Will, and the Principle of
Alternate Possibilities,” 267 68; and Scott MacDonald, “Egoistic Rationalism:
Aquinas' Basis for Christian Morality,” in Christian Theism and the Problems of
Philosophy, 333.
25. Friedrich Nietzsche, On the Genealogy
of Morals 1.1. Translations of Nietzsche will be taken from the editions of
Walter Kaufmann: (New York: Random House/Vintage Books). I will use the
traditional English abbreviations of Nietzsche's works: The Gay Science (GB);
Beyond Good and Evil (BGE); On the Genealogy of Morals (GM); Twilight of the
Idols (Tl); and The Will to Power (WP). In keeping with Kaufmann's caveats on
treating WP as a finished work, I will cite it only to amplify claims extracted
from Nietzsche's published works.
26. BGE 6; 32; 268; WP 481; 493.
27. BGE 6; GB 335. For an elaboration, see
Gilles Deleuze, Nietzsche and Philosophy, Hugh Tomlinson, trans. (New York:
Columbia University Press, 1983), 767.
28. TI 2.2.
29. BGE 186.
30. BGE 5.
31. BGE 13.
32. TI 6.7.
33. BGE 13; 36.
34. TI 2.5.
35. Jean Granier recognizes the “antinomy,”
but allows it to stand. See “Perspectivism and Interpretation,” in The New Nietzsche,
David B. Allison, ed. (New York: Dell Publishing Co., 1977), 19799. Harold
Alderman elevates the psychological while slighting the cosmological side of Nietzsche's
teaching. See Nietzsche's Gift (Athens: Ohio University Press, 1977), eh. 4.
Traey Strong proceeds similarly, downplaying the cosmological in favor of the psychological.
See “Text and Pretexts: Reflections on Perspectivism in Nietzsche,” Political
Theory 13 (May 1985): 17576. Gilles Deleuze, on the other hand, explains the psychological
in terms of the epistemological. See Nietzsche and Philosophy, eh. 2, especially
5155. Finally, Alexander Nehamas attempts a compromise which in the name of consistency
would dilute both sides of the teaching. See Nietzsche: Life As Literature
(Cambridge and London: Harvard University Press, 1985), eh. 2.
36. See BGE 22.
37. WP 567. See Deleuze, Nietzsche and
Philosophy, 3.
38. BGE 13. See too, GS 5.349.
39. BGE 22. See too, WP 481.
40. BGE 36. Nietzsche's use of the language
of belief reminds us again of the perspectival character of his account. Yet
note the tension involved in the transition from “our faith” to “the world
viewed from inside,” from the view from the subject to the view from nature.
Can both views be simultaneously maintained, as Nietzsche would have it and at
what cost, with what consequences or must we finally choose to reduce one to
the terms of the other?
41. See Deleuze, Nietzsche and Philosophy,
5051; 8586.
42. Deleuze, Nietzsche and Philosophy, 77,
citing WP 204.
43. GM 1.13.
44. TI 6.2.
45. GM 3.7. I recognize that I have adopted
a terminology foreign to Nietzsche's own exposition, hut I see no other way to
make this necessary point about his position. It remains significant that while
he cannot seem to eliminate it, Nietzsche himself fails or perhaps refuses to
recognize and articulate the distinction to which I advert.
46. GM Preface.2.
47. BGE 3; 9; 21; GS Preface.2; 6.301.
48. BGE 6.
49. BGE 19. This section is a miniature
treatise on will as function.
50. BGE 19.
51. TI VI.3; GS V.360.
52. GM 1.13; TI 6.7.
53. BGE 21.
54. It should be emphasized that our
examination is concerned with the functions of intellect and will alone, and so
abstracts from much that Nietzsche himself includes in his account of human
acts the role of the passions for example, or as Nietzsche sometimes puts it,
of those other than intellect and will. Any complete treatment of his position
would need to integrate what I have consciously excluded.
55. BGE 19.
56. BGE 19; 21; 23; see Deleuze, Nietzsche
and Philosophy, 53.
57. BGE 17; GM 1.13; TI 3.5.
58. Stanley Rosen has provocatively argued
that, given Nietzsche's account of the universality of will to power's
causality, such exhortations and denunciations form only the exoteric surface
of Nietzsche's teaching. They are rhetorical support for the false but salutary
belief that human action is free, in the absence ofwhich belief human beings
would soon fall into despair. See The Ancients and the Moderns (New Haven and
London: Yale University Press, 1989), 197-200.
59. Thus the centrality in Nietzsche's
thinking of the affirmation of the eternal return of the same as the pinnacle
of freedom.
60. See Rosen, The Ancients and the
Moderns, 195,21920.
61. TI 2.5.
62. Cf. Alasdair MacIntyre, Three Rival
Versions of Moral Enquiry: Encyclopedia, Genealogy and Tradition (Notre Dame:
University of Notre Dame Press, 1990), 4546.
No comments:
Post a Comment