Fr. Austin Fagothey, S.J., “Right
And Reason,” pp. 251-265
CHAPTER 23
THE FAMILY
DOMESTIC SOCIETY
If
any group of human beings has the right to be called a society, that group is
the family. In ancient times the family included all close blood relatives and
not merely those who lived together; the word was also used to mean a whole
household, including servants and other nonrelated persons, so long as they
lived under one roof or on the same plantation. We take the more restricted
meaning of the word: the family is a society consisting of husband or father,
wife or mother, and their children.
The
family or domestic society consists of two components or subsocieties: a
horizontal component, the union of husband and wife, called conjugal society;
and a vertical component, the union of parents and children, called parental
society. These are not really two distinct societies, but two aspects or
directions within the family. Accidentally a family may have one component
only, but this is not the normal case.
The
material cause of the family, as of all societies, consists of the members or
persons constituting it: a man, a woman, and the children born from them. The
formal cause is the moral bond between them, consisting of a definite group of
rights and duties, guaranteed by contract in conjugal society and imposed by
the nature of things in parental society. The final cause of the family is the
good of all parties concerned, but especially of the child which is the natural
product of relations between the sexes. The efficient cause of the family is
the contract of marriage, or more properly the contracting parties, for by marriage
the family is brought into existence and maintained.
MARRIAGE
Marriage
may be considered as the act of getting married (wedding) or as the state of
being married (wedlock). The first is the marriage contract, by which a man and
a woman give and receive rights over each other's body for the performance of
the generative act. As a state, marriage is a society or lasting union of a man
and a woman resulting from such a contract. These define marriage not at its
best, but in its bare essentials. We shall consider the state of marriage
first, for people get married in order to live in the married state; hence the
nature and conditions of the contract are determined from the state that the
contract aims to produce.
The
state of marriage implies four chief conditions:
1.
There must be a union of opposite sexes. Since marriage has to do with the
reproduction of the human race, this requirement is obvious. Thus marriage is
opposed to all forms of unnatural sexual behavior. Whether marriage is always
between only one man and only one woman will be discussed later.
2.
Marriage is a permanent union. It must last at least as long as is necessary
for the fulfillment of its primary purpose, the begetting and rearing of
children. Hence it must endure at least until the last child is capable of
living an independent life. Thus marriage differs from promiscuity. Whether
marriage involves lifelong permanence will be considered later.
3.
It is an exclusive union. The partners agree to share relations only with each
other, so that extramarital acts are a violation of justice. Thus adultery is a
crime against marriage.
4.
Its permanence and exclusiveness are guaranteed by contract. Mere living
together without being bound to do so does not constitute marriage, even though
the partners actually remain together for life, because they do not form a
society. This contract makes the difference between marriage and concubinage.
PROBLEM
The
above is only a description of what marriage means as an actually existing institution.
But ever since the beginning of ethics and the Greeks' first probing into human
customs, the question was raised whether marriage is a natural institution
necessary for the human race or only the prevailing convention we have grown to
accept as a matter of course. If the former, marriage is the only possible
arrangement between the sexes in conformity with the moral law; if the latter,
marriage may still be the most desirable arrangement but not the only possible
one even from the ethical standpoint. If marriage is a natural institution, the
family is a natural society; otherwise it is not. The importance of the
question is obvious:
(1)
Is marriage merely a human convention?
(2)
Is marriage a natural institution?
Evolutionists
as a group, and all modern materialists must be evolutionists, hold that man
gradually developed from primitive promiscuity through various forms of
polygamy to the monogamous marriage, the stage corresponding to his present
development; future evolution will probably lead on to some more advanced
arrangement; hence, though man is naturally social in a broad sense, marriage
is a purely human institution that may be abandoned for something better. Those
moral positivists who hold that man is not naturally social should logically
deny that the family is a natural society, but they seem to be thinking rather
of the state than of the family in this connection; at any rate Rousseau1 says that the family is the only natural
society. Those who hold that marriage is merely conventional may, motivated
perhaps by personal reasons, advocate the abolition of the convention in favor
of freer relations between the sexes, or they may think that on utilitarian
grounds it is an excellent convention by all means to be maintained.
On
the other hand, the thesis that marriage is a natural institution, besides
expressing the prevailing and traditional belief, is the only one that can
square with the natural law. A system of ethics based on the natural law, as
ours is, has but to establish the connection between marriage and the natural
law, in order to show that marriage is no mere convention but a natural
institution.
MARRIAGE A NATURAL
INSTITUTION
Aristotle's
sagacious words deserve quoting because they contain the germ of our argument
as well as a penetrating insight into human nature:
Between
man and wife friendship seems to exist by nature; for man is naturally inclined
to form couples—even more than to form cities, inasmuch as the household is
earlier and more necessary than the city, and reproduction is more common to
man with the animals.2 With the other animals the union extends only to this
point, but human beings live together not only for the sake of reproduction but
also for the various purposes of life; from the start the functions are
divided, and those of man and woman are different; so they help each other by
throwing their peculiar gifts into the common stock. It is for these reasons
that both utility and pleasure seem to be found in this kind of friendship. But
this friendship may be based also on virtue, if the parties are good; for each
has its own virtue and they will delight in the fact. And children seem to be a
bond of union (which is the reason why childless people part more easily); for
children are a common good to both and what is common holds them together.3
The
Thomistic proof is built on this passage but casts the idea into a more formal
type of argument:
That
is said to be natural to which nature inclines, although it comes to pass
through the intervention of the free will; thus acts of virtue and the virtues
themselves are called natural; and in this way matrimony is natural, because
natural reason inclines thereto in two ways. First, in relation to the
principal end of matrimony, namely the good of the offspring. For nature
intends not only the begetting of offspring, but also its education and
development until it reach the perfect state of man as man, and that is the
state of virtue. Hence, according to the Philosopher4 we derive three things from our parents,
namely existence, nourishment, and education. Now a child cannot be brought up
and instructed unless it have certain and definite parents, and this would not
be the case unless there were a tie between the man and a definite woman, and
it is in this way that matrimony consists. Secondly, in relation to the
secondary end of matrimony, which is the mutual services which married persons
render one another in household matters. For just as natural reason dictates
that men should live together, since one is not self-sufficient in all things
concerning life, for which reason man is described as being naturally inclined
to political society, so too among those works that are necessary for human
life some are becoming to men, others to women. Wherefore nature inculcated
that society of man and woman which consists in matrimony.5
The
argument may be restated in the following fashion, carrying it along by steps
and bringing out each point expressly:
1.
Nature intends the continuance of the human race, because nature has given
human beings the faculty and instinct for reproduction. Nature intends that
this occur by a union of man and woman, because human beings are made to
reproduce in the sexual manner. Hence in nature's plan the first and
fundamental purpose of the sexual relation is the child. People may marry for a
variety of motives, for love, for companionship, for money, for position. The
idea of begetting children may be very secondary, perhaps only tolerated rather
than desired, in the minds of many marrying couples; it need not be
psychologically uppermost in their minds. But there is no doubt that it is
primary in nature's design. Men eat mostly for the pleasure of it and rarely
think of its necessity for sustaining life, yet they recognize on reflection
that the latter is the primary purpose of eating. The same is true regarding
the sexual relation; it may be done for pleasure, but its primary purpose is to
sustain the race. In race-preservation, nature has not trusted to logic by
which man might reason to his duty in this regard, but has implanted an
instinct so strong that most human beings follow it. Thus the whole economy of
nature in establishing the sexes leads to the child.
2.
The duty of caring for the child naturally devolves on the parents. The parents
are the cause of the child's existence and therefore are charged with caring
for its welfare. There is nothing so helpless as the human infant. Some animals
can fend for themselves shortly after birth, and none require a long period of
care. Natural instinct prompts the parent animals, when both are necessary, to
remain together until the offspring are sufficiently reared to care for
themselves. In no case does this last until the next mating season, and
therefore promiscuous mating does no harm to the offspring of animals and
allows well for the fulfillment of nature's primary purpose. The same cannot be
said of human beings. The human child cannot live at all without intense care
for several years, and on the whole needs about twenty years of rearing before
it is really able to live a fully independent human life. The ones equipped by
nature with the means for rearing the child and normally impelled to it by
natural instinct and love are the parents. Other agencies are poor makeshifts
in this regard. Therefore the parents are designated by nature as the child's
proper guardians.
3.
The duty of rearing the child belongs to both parents, and not to one alone.
That this duty belongs to the mother is clear from the fact that she must bear
the child and nurse it; otherwise it cannot survive even the first few days of
life. But the father is equally the cause of the child's existence, and
therefore is equally charged by nature with the child's welfare. Together they
gave the child life and together they must care for it, not in lives apart and
independent, but in that joint life which makes up the society of the family.
Ordinarily neither mother nor child can procure the means of subsistence, and
who else in nature's plan has this duty except the father, the one responsible
for the condition of mother and child? The possibility that the mother may have
wealth of her own is accidental and outside of nature's provision. The help of
the father is necessary, not only in the first years of the child's life, but
throughout the whole period of the child's rearing. In fact, it is rather
toward the latter part of the training period that the father's influence is
most necessary, when he must fit his children, especially the boys, to take
their place in human life. Nature has given father and mother different
capacities that are psychologically as well as physically complementary, and
the influence of the father's sternness as well as of the mother's sweetness is
necessary for the adequate training of the child.
From
these three points it follows that nature demands a permanent and exclusive
union between the sexes, and one guaranteed by contract, in other words, that
marriage is a natural institution. A momentary union for the sake of
procreation alone is a betrayal and gross violation of nature's provisions for
the human child. It also follows that any use of the sexual faculty outside
marriage is contrary to nature and to the natural law, for it either fails to
provide for the child or else is some form of unnatural perversion.
Remarks
on the Argument.—1. The argument shows why parents should remain together, but
why must they bind themselves to this by contract? Parental society requires no
contract, since the infant cannot make a contract and when it arrives at the
use of reason finds itself already a member of parental society by disposition
of nature itself. The same is not true of conjugal society, which is entered
into freely by adults. Each must be assured of the other partner's faithfulness
before assuming the heavy burdens that marriage entails. Public order as well
as the virtue of the two partners requires that it be publicly known who is
married to whom. Therefore a formal contract is necessary.
2.
If the argument for marriage as a natural institution is drawn wholly from the
parents' obligation to the child, what about childless marriages? The plan of
nature must be judged from the normal instance, not from what is accidental.
There is no marriage contract and no consequent married state unless the partners
transfer to one another rights, and assume toward one another duties, which in
the normal course of nature should issue in the existence of children. The
begetting and rearing of children remains the primary end of marriage, even if
through default of nature no child arrives. Nature sets the end, but does not
guarantee that it will be attained in every case. Childless couples form a
family in its conjugal relation, even though the parental relation never
becomes actualized. They have the same rights and duties toward one another as
any married people, but their duties as parents are in abeyance so long as they
have no child.
3.
Nature sometimes allows the child to be deprived of father or mother or both;
how then is the help of both required by nature? Here again the plan of nature
must be judged from the normal instance. A man can get through life on one leg
or without any, but this is not nature's design for the human frame. Loss of a
parent, and much more of both, is recognized as a great misfortune in the
child's life. An institution can supply material needs perhaps better than some
parents, but it cannot give the child the love it craves and all that goes to
make a home. Adoption into another family is the best remedy, but this supposes
that there should be families, the very thing we have been proving.
4.
If marriage is a natural institution, is it not contrary to nature not to
marry? Marriage is a duty for the race but not for the individual, since its
primary end is the racial and not the in dividual good. The individual's good
can be obtained only by the individual's effort; thus no man can live by
getting others to eat for him. But the good of the race can be obtained if a
sufficient number tend toward it. Marriage would be a duty for each individual
only if the human race would be in danger of dying out, but man's strong sexual
propensities leave no fear in this regard. But, though marriage is not
necessary for all, it is necessary for those who intend to have sexual
experience.
PRIMARY AND SECONDARY
ENDS OF MARRIAGE
As
we have seen, the primary end of marriage is the good of the race to be
achieved through the good of the children born of this particular union. It is
not only the begetting but also the rearing of children. Rearing or education
is taken here in the broadest sense for full physical, mental, and moral
development, by which the children are fitted to face life, to pursue their
last end, and to work with their fellows for the common good. This is the task
married couples take on themselves, which they alone can most properly
accomplish, and for which they bind themselves into a permanent contractual
society rather than a temporary indiscriminate union. This is why marriage is
marriage.
The
secondary ends, while not absolutely essential, reinforce the primary end. They
can be summed up in the mutual love and help which should exist between husband
and wife. More specifically:
1.
Sexual desire finds its only legitimate outlet in marriage. It is an utter
mistake to see anything wrong in sex itself, which is a merely natural power
and good in itself, but any use of it outside marriage is immoral. One who does
not marry is bound to continence, a form of life for the few rather than the
many.
2.
Human love is something on a far higher plane than animal desire, something
more lasting and spiritual, for it is directed to the other as a person with
qualities of mind, heart, and soul. Whereas sex seeks selfish pleasure, love is
the most unselfish thing in the world and seeks the good of the beloved. No
marriage can be perfect without it.
3.
Companionship results from the fact that the two sexes are ideally suited to
each other, since the qualities of man and woman are naturally supplementary,
each supplying what the other lacks. This mutual need appears in a practical as
well as in a romantic way, and many unemotional marriages are successful on
this prosaic level. Companionship remains long after the fires of passion are
burnt out.
4.
Self-perpetuation, the desire to leave behind an image of oneself, though
scarcely present before childbirth, becomes prominent afterward and is a
powerful motive in keeping the family together. It furnishes a new sense of
identity between man and wife when each sees that the image of oneself is also the
image of the other.
BIRTH CONTROL
Any
use of sex outside marriage is immoral, but there can also be immoral uses of
sex within marriage. Unnatural acts performed by husband and wife are wrong
from the very fact that they are unnatural. The only controversy on this point
regards the formerly rare but now widespread practice of birth control. Is this
also an unnatural act?
Birth
control is the popular but inexact term used to mean contraception, birth
prevention, or race suicide: the use of artificial means (mechanical, physical,
or chemical) to prevent conception that might result from the marriage act. As
taken here, it does not mean a control over births by abstinence or continence,
or the limitation of intercourse to periods when conception is less likely to
occur.
The
practice of artificial contraception is propagandized as a method of
counteracting overpopulation in countries that cannot support so many people,
as a means of relieving economic distress in families already too large, and as
a eugenic measure against the breeding of subnormal strains; but it seems to be
practiced chiefly by the higher social brackets of civilized countries.
However, our viewpoint is not economic or sociological, but ethical.
Hedonists,
utilitarians, relativists, and those moral positivists who base all morality on
convention have little or no opposition to this practice, since they see in man
no obligation rationally to conform his conduct to his nature. But in a natural
law philosophy there can be no defense for artificial contraception. The
argument has already been given in our proof that marriage is a natural
institution whose primary end is the begetting and rearing of children. This is
the purpose for which nature has equipped man with the faculty of reproduction.
Its use outside marriage is immoral, and even in marriage it is immoral
deliberately to frustrate the marriage act of its natural issue. To frustrate a
natural faculty of its primary purpose is to go against nature, to act in a
manner directly contrary to the norm of morality, and to do something
intrinsically wrong.
Artificial
birth control is wrong for the reason that it is an unnatural vice of the same
sort as solitary vice and homosexuality. These sins are attempts to secure
sexual satisfaction while at the same time evading the responsibilities which
nature attaches to this pleasure. The sexual power exists for the sake of the
race and its continuance. The strong desire animals, including the human
animal, feel for sex gratification is nature's means of alluring them to breed.
To seek the satisfaction while at the same time defrauding nature is what is
meant by perversion. Other animals, having no free will and guided only by
instinct, cannot abuse their faculties and there are no unnatural vices found
among them. Man alone is able to act unnaturally, but is bound not to do so by
the natural moral law.
Since
marriage is a natural institution, and artificial birth control is a violation
of the primary end of marriage, artificial birth control is against the natural
law. Hence it cannot be justified by eugenic, economic, sociological,
political, humanitarian, or any other reasons. The remedy is to alleviate the
economic and social situation, not to counsel sex perversion.
Are
then married people obliged to have as many children as possible? No, provided
they use no immoral means to prevent them. With mutual consent, husband and
wife are always allowed to refrain. Marriage transfers rights, and it is a
violation of the marriage contract to refuse these rights to the spouse who
seriously demands them, but there is no obligation to demand them. Marital
continence is not easy, but it is not as impossible as some seem to think.
What
of the so-called "rhythm" method? It differs from artificial contraception
in that no immoral means are used. Relations are limited to the comparatively
sterile periods that nature itself provides. Since there is no obligation to
demand marriage rights at all, there is no obligation to demand them at one
time rather than another. Hence in the "rhythm" method the particular
act done here and now is not performed unnaturally nor is there any obstacle
placed to its natural issue. It is known that the act will be unfruitful, but
nature itself has made it so. However, an act may be wrong not only because of
the means used but also because of the end intended. Partners who limit
relations to sterile periods exclusively would do so only because they intend
to avoid having children. To enter marriage with the fixed intention of avoiding
having any children under any circumstances is immoral, as robbing that
marriage of its primary purpose; such a contract would be invalid. But
accidental circumstances can arise which make the having of children
undesirable at least for a time. Such reasons are practically reducible to four
heads:
(1)
Medical, the health of one of the partners
(2)
Eugenic, a serious hereditary defect
(3)
Economic, inability to support a larger family
(4)
Social, such conditions as war or overpopulation
Two
other requirements must be met: both partners must agree to abstain during the
fertile period, and both must be able to do so without proximate danger of sin.
Since
the means is not wrong in itself, and so long as the intention is not mere
selfishness but the avoidance of a serious difficulty, the "rhythm"
method is a morally justifiable solution. It is not at all the ideal of family
relations, but, like other matters governed by the double effect principle, a
legitimate way of tolerating the less good when the greater good is
unattainable.
PROPERTIES OF MARRIAGE
Our
whole discussion up to this point has had to do with marriage in its bare
essentials. We have considered only those things without which the primary end
of marriage cannot be attained at all. But nature also demands that marriage
have certain properties that are necessary to attain the secondary ends, and to
attain the primary end in its fullness and perfection. We said before that
marriage must be between man and woman, but we did not say how many. We also
said that marriage must be lasting, but we did not say how long. These
questions are answered by the two main properties of marriage:
(1)
Unity, as opposed to polygamy
(2)
Indissolubility, as opposed to divorce
Polygamy.
—Unity of marriage means the marriage of only one man with only one woman at
the same time. Such a marriage is called monogamy; marriage to two at the same
time is bigamy; marriage to more than one at the same time without specifying
the number is polygamy. Polygamy is said of either sex; it is:
(1)
Polygyny, when one husband has more than one wife
(2)
Polyandry, when one wife has more than one husband
Polygyny
does not wholly frustrate the primary end of marriage. It places no hindrance
to the birth of children, and allows at least the essentials of the child's
rearing. Each mother can devote herself to the rearing of her own children
while supported by the father. Unless the number of wives is extremely large,
the father also should be able to assist somewhat in the training of the
children.
But
polygyny cannot realize the primary end of marriage perfectly, and can hardly
fulfill the secondary ends at all. The father cannot give the same attention to
the training of the children of several wives that he could give to those of
one wife. The mutual love and help that should exist between husband and wife
are weakened by being single in one direction and divided in the other. There
can be no equality between husband and wife when she is only one among several,
and there is little wonder that in polygamous countries the position of woman
is not far above that of a slave. Jealousy among the wives is hardly to be
avoided when each vies for the husband's favor and each is ambitious for her
own children. Almost superhuman ingenuity is required of the husband to be
perfectly fair to the wives and the children, and this kind of society seems
possible only when the woman's condition is so degraded that her will does not
count. All this is reflected on the children who grow up in such an atmosphere.
Polygynous
families, wanting in unity, love, dignity, and equality, make a poor foundation
for civil society which rests on the basis of the family. Though such evils may
occur in a monogamous family, they occur there only accidentally, through the
fault of the parties concerned and not through the nature of the institution;
but in a polygynous family these evils can be avoided only accidentally.
Polyandry
is opposed both to the primary and to the secondary ends of marriage, and is
therefore intrinsically wrong. In a sense polyandry is even worse than
promiscuity, for the parties bind themselves to everything that makes
promiscuity hideous. The only alleviating factor is that the several husbands
would all be pledged to the support of the one wife and all the children she
would have. Thus wife and children would be assured of material support, but
this is not the main element in marriage.
The
excuse of polygyny, quicker propagation of the race, is absent in polyandry,
for a woman cannot bear more children to many husbands than to one. The rearing
of the children as nature intends becomes impossible, because the father cannot
be determined with certainty and is thus unable to perform the function he has
in natural law. The child also, unable to know his father, cannot call on him
for help and guidance. The children would naturally quarrel over which husband
is the father of which child. All the fathers might try to fulfill these
functions to all the children or divide them arbitrarily, but this cannot be a
truly parental relation. The practical difficulties of conducting a
well-ordered family or home under polyandry are simply insuperable. Thus,
though practiced no doubt by individuals and by a few degraded tribes here and
there, it has never been the recognized form of marriage in any developed
society.
Divorce.
—The second property of marriage is indissolubility, which means that the
marriage cannot be dissolved, that it must last until the death of one of the
partners. Married persons may break up their home in either of two ways:
(1)
By separation from bed and board
(2)
By attempted dissolution of the marriage bond
A
separation, sometimes called imperfect divorce, means that the two parties
cease to live together and to discharge marital functions, but remain married;
the marriage bond remains intact so that neither party is free to contract a
new marriage. It is easy to see that such a separation is sometimes necessary,
but it should be undertaken only for the gravest of reasons, such as the danger
of physical harm, and under proper authority, lest personal whim play too great
a part as a motive. We are not speaking here of such separations, since they
are not intended to dissolve marriage.
The
term divorce is usually understood to mean perfect divorce, which is an attempt
to dissolve the marriage bond itself so that the parties are free to contract
new marriages with other per sons. This alone is our question here. Divorce,
like the marriage contract which it tries to dissolve, is regulated by
ecclesiastical and civil law. We are obliged to consider the matter from the
standpoint of the natural law alone, a limitation that necessarily makes our
treatment incomplete. The primary end of marriage requires that the marriage
endure until the family is fully reared.
The
primary end of marriage, as we saw, is not only the begetting but also the
rearing of children. Therefore by the natural law marriage must last until this
end is accomplished, until the child is fully reared and able to live an
independent life of its own. To rear one child normally takes about twenty
years, more or less. But if the parents must live together for twenty years,
other children are ordinarily to be expected. Hence marriage must last for
about twenty years after the birth of the youngest child. The woman is capable
of bearing children up to the age of forty-five or so. Therefore normally
marriage must last until husband and wife are over sixty years old. This much
at least the primary end of marriage demands.
The
secondary ends of marriage require that the marriage last until the death of
one of the partners. When married people have reached this age, hardly any
reason could justify a separation. Life together could not have been too
intolerable. Most separations occur in the early years of marriage, in the
difficult period of mutual adjustment, when the romantic mist has blown away to
reveal each to the other in the hard light of reality. It would be absurd to
think that this has not already happened to an elderly couple who have shared
all the joys and sorrows of life together for so long. The man is the natural
support of the woman and must stand by her in her old age; the woman who has
given to her husband her whole period of youth, beauty, and fertility deserves
love and protection to the last. Likewise the woman who has taken her husband's
support and protection in the years of his strength cannot leave him to
loneliness at the end. Children, also, are the natural heirs and have a claim
on the family property, which ought to be kept intact until by the parents'
death it passes to them. And what kind of rearing would parents give to their
children if they ruined it all by the bad example of breaking up their own home
in their old age?
The
chief reason against divorce is the havoc it works in the life of the child.
Parents who divorce one another are considering themselves only, and ignoring
the child whose good is the primary end of marriage. The child is the one who
pays for the parents' selfishness. There is no substitute for the home. Parents
who break up the home deprive the child of the environment in which by the
intention of nature it should grow up. Cases happen in which the child profits
by being removed from a bad home, but nature considers what is normal, not what
is accidental. In fact, how can a home be bad except through the moral fault of
at least one of the parents?
From
this examination of the primary and secondary ends of marriage it follows that
divorce is opposed to the natural law. In the early years of marriage husband
and wife are forbidden to break the contract and seek new partners by the
common duty they have toward the children nature normally supplies. In the
latter years of marriage no justifying reason can be found for breaking the
bond that has actually lasted so long.
Must
we say that divorce is intrinsically wrong, so that no case of it can be
permitted for any reason? Not absolutely, but conditionally. Divorce, being so
contrary to the fundamental purposes of marriage and so serious a social evil,
is intrinsically wrong if done at the mere discretion of the parties concerned.
It is not intrinsically wrong if authorized by God, who in His providence can
avert the naturally expected evil consequences. Can we prove by human reasoning
on purely philosophical grounds either that God does or that He does not
communicate this authority by the natural law to civil society? There seems to
be no positive evidence to show that He does. On the other hand, conclusive
evidence to show that He does not had best be sought from theological sources.
A similar judgment applies to polygyny also.
QUESTIONS
ON THE ARGUMENT.— The following difficulties are implicitly answered in the
argument, but, because of the importance of the matter, should be given
definite formulation:
1.
If marriage is a free contract, why can it not be freely terminated at the
pleasure of the contracting parties? Marriage is a free contract in the sense
that one may either marry or not, but the conditions of marriage are laid down
by nature and nature's Author, not by the contracting parties. Even in other
matters the terms of a contract can be set down by law, either natural or
positive; thus, one is free to enlist in the army, but having done so must
serve out the term of enlistment. The term for marriage, set by the natural
law, is until the death of one of the partners.
2.
Why be obliged to spend the rest of one's life with a companion one has ceased
to love? Why cannot an unfortunate mistake be rectified? Such questions only go
to show what an important step marriage is. Those who enter it hastily with no
sense of its serious obligations must pay the price of their folly. A contract
for life is precisely that, and a person is obliged to live up to his word.
Accidentally divorce may be better for this or that individual, but it is
ruinous to mankind generally. Laws are made for the common good, and
individuals are bound to cooperate for the common good even at personal
disadvantage.
3.
Would not such difficulties be obviated by trial marriages or companionate
marriages? These are not marriages at all, but legalized concubinage with an
option for future promiscuity. They cannot properly fulfill the primary end of
marriage, as the arguments we have already given sufficiently show.
4.
If separation without remarriage is allowable for serious reasons, why should
not divorce with remarriage be allowable for the same reasons, since in both
cases the family is broken up? The difference here is in the intention of the
separating partners. The first case does not involve the plan of subsequent
marital infidelity, whereas the second case almost always does. The first case
is a misfortune of the kind that occurs when one partner goes insane or is sent
to prison; the second case is an immoral desire to form a new union with a more
desirable person by violating the contract made with the first.
5.
Why could not divorce be restricted to extreme cases such as adultery? In this
matter the slightest entering wedge soon throws the door wide open. In those
states where this is the only permitted cause for divorce, adultery is
deliberately committed or simulated to obtain a divorce. Elsewhere the barriers
have been gradually let down until the most trifling excuses are accepted. This
so-called wedge argument has its value and is confirmed by history, but the
only satisfactory answer to this question must be sought from theological
sources.
6.
Why should not divorce be allowed in sterile marriages, since in them the
primary end of marriage cannot be attained? Here again we must note that nature
plans for the normal, not for the exceptional case. It is true that in sterile
marriages the primary end cannot be attained, but this is the fault of nature,
not of the parties concerned. The secondary ends of marriage remain, and they
are sufficient for entering the married state so long as the primary end is not
deliberately hindered. Nature seems to indicate that for the propagation of the
race not all marriages need be fertile. Most couples when marrying do not know
whether they are sterile or not, and cannot be sure for many years; yet from
the outset, like any other married people, they must be assured of their
partner's faithfulness. Even known sterility is not a bar to marriage, for a
sterile person can fulfill the contract, which transfers a right to the
generative act itself but not to actual fertility, the later being nature's
gift and not within the contracting party's power. The wedge argument applies
here also; some would induce sterility to obtain a divorce, and lesser causes
would be gradually admitted.
7.
Cannot the new husband or wife of a divorced person help in raising the
children? In some cases they can do so quite well, but in many cases they are
bitterly resented by the children. Stepfathers and step-mothers are a byword,
not because there are no successful ones, but because in general they are
unable to take the dead parent's place. The case is vastly complicated when the
real parent is still alive.
8.
People who have no intention of marrying again sometimes get a civil divorce;
is this wrong? The civil law makes no distinction between a separation and a
divorce, declaring that the marriage contract is considered dissolved before
the law, and leaving it to the individual conscience to decide whether it is
really dissolved or not. People who intend only a separation may sometimes be
obliged to secure a civil divorce to protect themselves from the other party,
to obtain support and custody of the children, or to effect a civilly valid
distribution of property. Divorce in these cases touches only the civil effects
of marriage, but it should have ecclesiastical as well as civil authorization.
THE MARRIAGE CONTRACT
The
married state of individuals begins by a contract entered into by the mutual
free consent of the man and the woman. People are not born married and may
remain unmarried throughout their lives. Nature does not select the partners
for marriage. There must be something that determines whether one shall marry
and whom one shall marry. Since nature does not determine it, the partners
themselves do, and they do it by the marriage contract.
The
marriage contract is a contract in the full sense of the word, and must fulfill
all the conditions requisite for a contract in general, as well as some
peculiar to itself. It is a bilateral onerous contract, by which the parties
transfer to each other strict rights and thereby incur toward each other strict
duties, which they henceforth owe to each other in justice. The essential right
transferred is the right to the use of the other person's body for the
performance of the generative act. Love, cohabitation, support, sharing of
goods, and the like are consequent rights. The transference of the essential
right is permanent and exclusive; failure to make it so invalidates the
contract.
By
its very nature as a contract marriage requires mutual free consent, and the
absence of error and fear. Freedom of consent is particularly important in
marriage, because marriage supposes love and love cannot be extorted, besides
the fact that marriage imposes heavy burdens which no one is obliged to assume,
much less to assume in company with a particular person.
An
impediment to marriage is some inability in the contracting party that makes
the marriage contract either invalid or illicit. The first kind render the
contract null and void from the beginning so that the parties never were
actually married. The second kind simply make it wrong for a person to marry
under such conditions, but if he does so the marriage contract holds. The chief
invalidating impediments in natural law are impotence, too close kinship, and
being already married. The Church, because of its control over marriage in the
supernatural order, and the state, for the sake of the common good, can
establish additional impediments of either grade.
The
ban of kinship may need a few remarks. The crime of incest has always been
regarded even by pagans with particular horror. Any marriage between parent and
child is absolutely outlawed by nature as utterly opposed to the parental
relation already existing. Marriage between brother and sister is not
absolutely contrary to the natural law, but is under even more stringent
conditions than polygyny and divorce; only God could allow it, and He would do
so only if otherwise the race could not propagate. The reason for banning
marriage between brother and sister is the fact that they grow up in the same
home, and develop during their immaturity a kind of love free from all passion;
anything else would mean the utter ruin of the family and make the home an
unlivable place.
1 Social
Contract, bk. I, ch. 2.
2 "Reproduction
is more common to man with the animals" than forming cities is common to
them. Reproduction is common to man and all animals, but political or
quasi-political organization is common to man and some animals only, such as
bees and ants.
3 Aristotle,
Nicomachean Ethics, bk. VIII, ch. 12, 1162a 16-28.
4 Ibid.,
ch. 11, 1161a 17.
5 St.
Thomas, Summa Theologica, III, Supplement, q. 41, a. 1. St. Thomas died before
he could complete the Summa Theologica. The Supplement was added by his
followers from others of his writings.
CONCLUSION
There is nothing in
human life more capable of abuse and mismanagement than sex. What is governed
so easily and naturally in animals by means of their instinct must be regulated
in man by his free will guided by his reason. Success or failure in life
depends to a very great extent on the individual's ability to control this
strongest of all passions. Marriage is the institution demanded by nature for
securing this control. Any number of otherwise successful people have wrecked
their lives by failing to succeed in their relations with the opposite sex. The
selecting of the right partner in life and the preservation of fidelity to the
marriage vow are not matters of accident but of wise human conduct. Marriage
also requires traits of character that are not accidentally achieved, but must
be sedulously developed. Success in the married state is possible only by the
practice of the cardinal virtues, prudence, justice, fortitude, and temperance,
in a high degree. Marriage therefore calls for a virtuous life and entails
heavy responsibilities, but it also brings with it one of the best of earthly
rewards, the founding and maintenance of a happy home.
SUMMARY
The
family, the most primitive society, consists of two subsocieties: conjugal, the
husband-wife relation, and parental, the parent-child relation. Marriage, which
creates and maintains the family, means both the contract and the resulting
state. The married state supposes a man and a woman united by contract in a
permanent and exclusive union whose primary purpose is the begetting and
rearing of children.
Is
marriage merely a human convention or a natural institution? That it is the
only arrangement between the sexes permitted by the natural law is proved thus:
(1)
Nature's design in establishing sex is the propagation of the race, and is
primarily directed to the child.
(2)
The duty of caring for the child they beget falls on the parents, and this
takes about twenty years.
(3)
The rearing of the child belongs to both parents jointly; the father owes not
only support but active help.
Therefore
nature demands a permanent and exclusive union guaranteed by contract; that is,
the natural law demands marriage.
While
the primary end of marriage is the begetting and rearing of children, there are
also secondary ends: to satisfy man's craving for sexual pleasure, human love,
companionship, and self-perpetuation.
Birth
control, in the sense of artificial contraception, is an unnatural use of sex
within marriage, a frustration of a natural faculty, and therefore immoral.
Eugenic, economic, social, political, and other reasons cannot justify it
ethically. The "rhythm" method, since it is not unnatural, is allowable
under certain conditions.
Marriage
has two main properties: unity and indissolubility. Polygamy, opposed to unity,
has two forms.
Polygyny,
one husband with several wives, makes the primary end of marriage difficult as
to the rearing of the children, and the secondary ends practically
unattainable. Polyandry, one wife with several husbands, renders all the ends
of marriage impossible. Both are against the natural law, especially the
latter.
Divorce,
opposed to indissolubility, means not a mere separation but an attempted
dissolution of the marriage bond, so as to leave the partners free to remarry.
The primary end of marriage requires the partners to remain together until the
last child is reared; since they are then over sixty years old, no justifying
reason can be found for breaking the marriage. Accidentally divorce may not be
harmful in individual cases, but it would be ruinous to mankind generally.
Nature legislates for the common good and all must keep nature's laws.
The
marriage contract is a bilateral onerous contract, by which each transfers to
the other the right to the generative act. It must fulfill all the requisites
for contracts in general regarding the contracting parties, the matter, and the
mutual consent. Any fault in the essentials of the contract renders it invalid.
The Church and the state may establish additional impediments rendering the
contract either invalid or illicit.
READINGS
This is as good a place
as any to suggest a reading of Aristotle's whole treatise on Friendship in the
Nicomachean Ethics, books VIII and IX, though there are only passing remarks on
marriage. Read his refutation of Plato's community of women in the Politics,
bk. II, ch. 1-4, 1260b28 to 1262b35.
The treatise on
marriage in the Summa Theologica, part III Supplement, qq. 41-68, is written
from the standpoint of a theologian but discusses the philosophical aspect
especially in qq. 41, 44-48, 51, 54, 65, 67. These are not found in the Basic
Writings.
Read Farrell's comments
in his Companion to the Summa, vol. IV, ch. VIII.
The two Papal
Encyclicals, Leo XIII's Arcanum (Christian Marriage) and Pius XI's Casti
Connubii (Christian Marriage) should certainly be read.
Handren, No Longer Two,
is a commentary on Casti Connubii.
Cronin, Science of
Ethics, vol. II, ch. XIII, XIV.
Rickaby, Moral
Philosophy, pp. 263-277.
Moore, Principles of
Ethics, ch. 16-19.
Leibell, Readings in
Ethics, pp. 763-788, 820-848.
Messner, Social Ethics,
bk. II, pt. I.
Haas, Man and Society,
ch. VI, VII.
Le Buffe and Hayes, The
American Philosophy of Law, pp. 272-287.
Sheed, Society and
Sanity, ch. 8-10.
The following have a
good philosophical background:
Wayne, Morals and
Marriage, an excellent little book for those contemplating marriage.
Schmiedeler, Marriage
and the Family.
Von Hildebrand's two
short books, Marriage and In Defense of Purity, are well worth reading.
Leclercq, Marriage and
the Family.
Joyce, Christian
Marriage.
Healy, Marriage
Guidance.
Clemens, Marriage and
the Family.
Gerrard, Marriage and
Parenthood.
Mihanovich, Schnepp,
Thomas, Marriage and the Family.
Thibon, What God Has
Joined Together.
Hope, Life Together.
Morrison, God is Its
Founder.
Magner, The Art of
Happy Marriage.
Foerster, Marriage and
the Sex Problem.
De Guchteneere's
Judgment on Birth Control; Moore, Birth Control; D'Arcy, Christian Morals, pp. 124-139.
There is a large pamphlet literature on this topic.
Thomas, Marriage and
Rhythm.
No comments:
Post a Comment