V. THE THEOLOGY OF
CHALCEDON
Chalcedon and Nicaea
The Acts of
Chalcedon often refer to the great theologians of the past as the ‘fathers’
(first at I. 10), a usage that developed after the Council of Nicaea of 325 to
refer to the bishops at Nicaea and to those theologians, earlier or later, who
bore witness to the Nicene faith. Fidelity to the Nicene Creed was indeed a
leitmotif of the Council of Chalcedon, where it was repeatedly insisted that
the Nicene Creed contains the whole orthodox understanding of God and Christ in
a nutshell, with the result that later texts can be no more than commentaries
upon it.202
The clearest
indication, perhaps, of the mind of the majority of the bishops who attended
the Council and acclaimed the Chalcedonian Definition is to be found in the
Codex Encyclius of the emperor Leo I. The year 457 saw the death of the emperor
Marcian, who had masterminded the Council six years earlier. The council’s
opponents in Alexandria took advantage of the situation to overthrow and lynch
their pro-Chalcedonian patriarch Proterius, and to elect in his place Timothy
Aelurus, an uncompromising anti-Chalcedonian.203 Both the pro-Chalcedonians and the anti-Chalcedonians
of Egypt appealed to the rest of the Christian world for support. The new emperor
Leo decided on an extensive consultation: he wrote to Pope Leo and to all the
metropolitan bishops in his dominions, requesting honest and conscientious
answers to the questions: what should be done about Timothy, and what should be
said about Chalcedon? The bishops, deeply shocked by the murder of Proterius,
answered overwhelmingly against Timothy and in favour of Chalcedon; 470 of them
signed letters to this effect (according to Photius), with only the bishops of
a single province (Pamphylia Secunda) partly dissenting. The emperor approved
their judgement, and issued their replies in a document known as the Codex
Encyclius. Half of it survives in an early Latin translation.204
The reason
why the Codex Encyclius has not been used as a guide to the meaning of the
Definition is that it is from the theological point of view a sadly
disappointing document. The bishops show little inclination to discuss theology;
few of them offer any detailed comments on the contents of the Definition. One
characteristic of all the replies stands out prominently: all the bishops gave
their approval to Chalcedon on the grounds that it followed the Nicene Creed.
It is, of course, a familiar fact that the Definition begins by quoting this
creed, but modern commentators have been slow to appreciate the importance of
this for the interpretation of the text as a whole. In view of the reluctance
of the fathers to approve any new definition, on the grounds that the Seventh
Canon of the Council of Ephesus205
had forbidden the use of any formulary of the faith beyond the Nicene Creed,
the composers of the Definition were obviously concerned to claim that it was
based on the creed. Did the statement reiterated so monotonously in 457/8 that
Chalcedon had confirmed Nicaea mean anything more than that Chalcedon was
orthodox? Modern historians of the development of doctrine would consider it
absurd to suppose that Nicaea had solved the Christological problem in advance:
its creed does indeed contain an article on the incarnation, but this consists
of no more than a simple affirmation of the doctrine, expressed in wholly traditional
language.
The question
that needs to be asked, however, is how the bishops of 457 viewed the matter.
If they had agreed with modern interpretation that sees no solution to the
fifth-century debate in the early fourth-century formula, it would have been
vacuous to argue, as they all did, that the teaching of Chalcedon was orthodox
because it was Nicene. Clearly, they thought that Nicaea contained an implicit
refutation of the errors that Chalcedon was concerned to condemn – the heresies
of Nestorius and Eutyches. An argument that Nicaea had implicitly condemned
Eutyches even before the unfortunate heresiarch had been born was spelt out in
the Address to Marcian published in the proceedings of the council (our
Documents after the Council 1). This text argues that the affirmation in the
creed that Christ ‘was enfleshed’ means that he truly assumed our flesh from
the Virgin, while the affirmation that Christ ‘became a human being’ expresses
that he assumed not only a human body
but also a rational soul. Likewise, the bishops of Syria Prima, in their reply
to the emperor Leo’s consultation, argued that the Eutychian denial that Christ
shared our nature is refuted by the teaching of the creed on the incarnation.206 Nicaea had
condemned Eutyches in advance, and therefore in order to condemn Eutyches all Chalcedon
had to do was to reaffirm Nicaea. This means that the full quotation of the
Nicene Creed at the beginning of the Definition should not be brushed aside, as
in most modern commentaries on the text, as if it were a mere preface, a pious
declaration of orthodox intent, before the Definition gets on to the real work.
The close
connection that the council asserted between its own work and the Nicene Creed
relates to its own conception of its task, which was not to achieve progress in
theological understanding but to define the limits of Nicene orthodoxy; this
stress on tradition did not represent intellectual sclerosis but rather an
awareness that the task of a council in defining orthodoxy and the task of a
theologian in developing doctrine are two quite different things. The Second
Council of Ephesus of 449 had condemned Flavian of Constantinople less for
heresy than for setting up a new doctrinal test as a requirement for full
membership of the Christian Church. The fathers of Chalcedon accepted a new
doctrinal definition only because it sought to uphold and protect the faith of
Nicaea, shared by all members of the church.207 The penalty of not only degradation but also
excommunication imposed on Dioscorus of Alexandria at the third session of the
council may seem chillingly severe, but the concern of the bishops was to
preserve the faith affirmed at every baptism and expressed in each celebration
of the eucharist.208 It was the unity of the rites of initiation into the
church and the foundations of Christian community that Chalcedon was concerned
to maintain, not some academic ideal of precise definition and intellectual progress.
Indeed, a modern reader who comes to the Acts in quest of illumination about
the niceties of Chalcedonian Christology will be disappointed by the lack of
theological debate worthy of the name.
Whatever
claims were made for the Nicene Creed as a perfect expression of faith in
Christ, needing no more than precise interpretation to counter later heresies,
it can be argued, however, that so far from solving the Christological problem
in advance it actually accentuated it. As interpreted by the end of the fourth
century, the teaching of the Council of Nicaea on the consubstantiality of
Father and Son implied so strong a doctrine of the Son’s full divinity as to
highlight the problem of how a single being could be both God and man. Christ
as God is timeless, immutable, omniscient, impassible (that is, incapable of
suffering), while Christ as man was created in time, underwent the changes
attendant on human life, confessed himself ignorant of some things (notably of
the day and hour of the end; Mt. 24:36), and suffered on the cross. All the
theologians in the Nicene tradition acknowledged the paradox and mystery of
this conjunction. All were agreed that Christ possesses two sets of contrasting
attributes and yet remains a single person. The Chalcedonian doctrine of one
Christ, who is acknowledged in two natures that unite to form a single person,
was to this extent common property.
The key final
section of the Definition runs as follows (V. 34):
Following,
therefore, the holy fathers, we all in harmony teach confession of one and the
same Son our Lord Jesus Christ, the same perfect in Godhead and the same
perfect in manhood, truly God and the same truly man, of a rational soul and body,
consubstantial with the Father in respect of the Godhead, and the same consubstantial
with us in respect of the manhood, like us in all things apart from sin,
begotten from the Father before the ages in respect of the Godhead, and the same
in the last days for us and for our salvation from the Virgin Mary the Theotokos
in respect of the manhood, one and the same Christ, Son, Lord, Only-begotten,
acknowledged in two natures without confusion, change, division, or separation
(the difference of the natures being in no way destroyed by the union, but
rather the distinctive character of each nature being preserved and coming
together into one person and one hypostasis), not parted or divided into two
persons, but one and the same Son, Only-begotten, God, Word, Lord, Jesus Christ,
even as the prophets from of old and Jesus Christ himself taught us about him
and the symbol of the fathers has handed down to us.
Before
attempting an interpretation of this text, we need to set it in the context of
the Christological controversy of the preceding 25 years.
Antiochene and Alexandrian Christology
In the period
before Chalcedon, there were two leading schools of Christological inquiry in
the Greek east.209 The Antiochene school of Syrian theologians, of whom
the most controversial was Nestorius (d. 450/1) and the most gifted Theodore of
Mopsuestia (d. 428) and Theodoret of Cyrrhus (d. c. 466), was concerned to
protect the changelessness of Christ’s Godhead and at the same time to give
scope for the freedom of his manhood; this led to a stress on the distinction
between the two constituent elements in Christ, Godhead and manhood.210 They therefore
used such formulae as ‘two natures’, ‘two hypostases’ (that is, two realities or
beings), even ‘two persons’, ‘conjoined’ (not mixed or blended) in ‘the person
of union’.211
Against them was soon ranged what is generally referred to as the Alexandrian
school, meaning in effect Cyril of Alexandria (bishop 412–444), developing the thought
of his great predecessor Athanasius (d. 373).212 Cyril gave prime emphasis to the unity of Christ,
which he expressed with such formulae as ‘one incarnate nature’, ‘one
hypostasis’, ‘two natures in contemplation alone’ (that is, distinct as we
describe them but not separate in reality), ‘one after the union’,213 ‘one from two’, and the like. Cyril did not
deny that the natures united in Christ preserve their differences, but he
insisted that they were no longer two ontologically distinct realities. Since
both sides agreed that Christ is both God and man ‘without confusion, change,
division, or separation’ (to use the famous expression in the Definition), the
argument over terminology was sterile, and can give the impression that both
sides really agreed but were keen to disguise the fact.
However,
there was more substance to the debate than this. Modern theologians contrast
‘Christology from below’, which makes the humanity of Christ its main concern,
and ‘Christology from above’, which presents the divine Son or Word who
‘became’ or ‘indwelt’ flesh (see John 1:14). However much theologians today may
assert that both approaches are valid and need to complement, not oppose, each
other, they certainly produce two very different pictures of Christ. In the
period before Chalcedon, the Antiochene school presented a Christology from
below, while the Alexandrian school presented a Christology from above. It is
in their gospel commentaries that the difference comes across most clearly.
Compare, for example, how Theodore of Mopsuestia and Cyril of Alexandria
comment on the verse, ‘I, when I am lifted up from the earth, will draw all men
to myself’ (John 12:32):
[Theodore] He
says: ‘I do not trust in my own strength, but through the nature which indwells
in me I hope to conquer Satan … God the Word made me his own once and for all
time when he assumed me; and it is clear that he will not leave me to act at
random. When therefore the God of all hears our judgement and sees that Satan
has inflicted death on me unjustly and undeservedly, abusing his tyranny against
me, he will order me to be freed from the bonds of death, with the result that
I shall then have confidence to pray to God for all the children of my race, so
that those who share with me in the same nature may also participate in the resurrection.’214
[Cyril]
Christ alone, as God, was able to procure all good things for us … Christ draws
[human beings] to himself and does not, like the disciples, lead them to another.
Here he shows himself to be God by nature, in that he does not make a distinction
between himself and the Father; for it is through the Son that one is drawn to the
knowledge of the Father.215
The
consciousness of the Antiochene Christ is a human consciousness of the one who
recognizes the dignity he has received of being united to the eternal Son,
while the consciousness of the Alexandrian Christ is that of the divine mind
that has condescended to operate in a human being. Theodore’s Christ can even
address the Son in the second person or refer to him in the third, as a
distinct personal subject. Meanwhile, Cyril was so influenced by Athanasius’ presentation
of Christ as a divine mind indwelling a human body that in his long series of
homilies on the Gospel of Luke he makes virtually no reference to Christ’s
human mind (or soul), even though he never doubted that he had one.
Accordingly, critics ancient and modern have faulted the Antiochenes for
offering an inadequate account of the unity of Christ, and have accused Cyril
of having an inadequate conception of his humanity. The Chalcedonian Definition
condemns Nestorius, as the representative of the dangers in Antiochene
Christology, for dividing Christ into ‘two sons’ or persons, one divine and the
other human, and condemns Eutyches, as the representative of a perversion to
which Alexandrian Christology was prone, of undermining the true humanity of
Christ.
And yet these
criticisms do both sides less than justice. So far from teaching that Christ is
a compound of two persons, a divine Son consubstantial with the Father and a
human son adopted by the Father as other human beings are, the Antiochenes insisted
that Christ is one Son, in whom the humanity is so lifted up as to share in the
relationship enjoyed by the eternal Son with his heavenly Father. At the same
time they insisted that Christians do not worship Christ’s Godhead while
venerating his manhood, but offer one and same worship to Christ, God and man.
In other words, although Christ in his internal constitution is a compound of
two distinct realities, he is one in his relationships both with the Father and
with the human race.216 At the same time, Cyril was able to accommodate human
limitations in Christ, even mental limitations, through developing the language
of St Paul about the self-emptying (kenôsis) through which the one who ‘was in
the form of God … took the form of servant, being born in the likeness of men’
(Phil. 2:6–7): as he wrote, Christ ‘has divine knowledge as the Wisdom of the
Father but, since he has put on the measure of ignorant humanity, in his
condescension he appropriates this together with the rest.’217 Cyril
repeatedly contrasted the reality of Christ’s divine powers with the
‘appearance’ of human limitations – not in the sense of a false appearance, but
in the sense that human nature is an ‘appearance’ in contrast to the
invisibility of the Godhead.218
Controversy and consensus
In the
context we have sketched of two Christological approaches, both of which had
their strengths and their internal correctives, the crucial question became,
which of the two was more faithful to the tradition of the Church? The
Christological controversy of the fifth century began in 428 when Nestorius, as
the newly installed bishop of Constantinople, publicly criticized the
attribution to the Virgin Mary of the title Theotokos (‘God-bearer’) on the
grounds that she gave birth not to the Godhead of Christ but to his humanity.
He was not perhaps aware that the title had been used by a number of pre-Nicene
and Nicene fathers, including Origen, Eusebius of Caesarea, and the
Cappadocians,219 but he could point out that it was not used in the Nicene
Creed; indeed this creed (in contrast to the Constantinopolitan Creed of 381)
makes no mention of Mary at all. Against these arguments Cyril insisted that
the Theotokos title was simply a corollary of the fact that Jesus’ human birth
is ascribed in the creed to the eternal Son – ‘one Lord Jesus Christ the Son of
God …, consubstantial with the Father …, who for us men and for our salvation
came down, was enfleshed and became man.’ He was therefore able to claim that
Nestorius was undermining the authority of the creed.
In developing
this argument in his Second Letter to Nestorius, written in February 430, Cyril
proceeded to defend the ascription of Christ’s human experiences to the eternal
Son:
He is spoken
of as begotten also according to the flesh from a woman, not as though his
divine nature received the beginning of its existence in the holy Virgin …; but
since for us and for our salvation he united manhood to himself hypostatically
and came forth from a woman, he is for this reason said to have been born in
the flesh. … He is said to have undergone fleshly birth, as making his own the
birth of his own flesh. So too we say that he both suffered and rose again, not
as though God the Word suffered in his own nature either blows or the piercing
of the nails or the other wounds (for the divine is impassible because it is also
incorporeal); but since it was the body that had become his own that suffered, he
himself again is said to have suffered these things for us, for the impassible
one was in the suffering body … So again, when his flesh was raised, the
resurrection is spoken of as his, not as though he fell into corruption (God
forbid!), but because again his own body was raised.220
Cyril’s
argument is cautious: he does not assert crudely that it was God the Word who was
born, suffered, died and rose again, but rather that he ‘is spoken of’ as the
subject of the human experiences. Since the eternal Son has made a human nature
his own, human attributes and experiences may appropriately be attributed to
the Godhead in credal profession. This is a defence of the classic communicatio
idiomatum – the expression of the union by ascribing to each nature what
strictly belongs to the other. In recognition of the duality in Christ, Cyril
is happy to use language that expresses the coexistence in Christ of two united
natures: ‘The Godhead and the manhood by their ineffable and indescribable
coming together into unity perfected for us the one Lord and Christ and Son …
He united manhood to himself … The impassible one was in the suffering body’
(ibid.).
It is this
that made possible the accord reached by Cyril and his Antiochene opponents
early in 433. The Antiochenes accepted the condemnation of Nestorius, while
Cyril proved his own moderation by accepting in his Letter to John of Antioch a
doctrinal statement drawn up by the Antiochene party, the Formula of Reunion,
of which the main part runs:
We therefore
acknowledge our Lord Jesus Christ, the only-begotten Son of God, perfect God
and perfect man made up of a rational soul and body, begotten from the Father
before the ages in respect of the Godhead and the same on the last day for us
and for our salvation from the Virgin Mary in respect of his manhood, the same
consubstantial with the Father in respect of the Godhead and consubstantial with
us in respect of the manhood. For there has occurred a union of two natures, and
therefore we acknowledge one Christ, one Son, one Lord. By virtue of this understanding
of the union which involves no merging, we acknowledge the holy Virgin to be
Theotokos, because God the Word was enfleshed and became man and from the very
conception united to himself the temple taken from her.221
Cyril’s
understanding of the ‘two natures’ in Christ was different from that of the
Antiochenes: he came to insist that the two natures are ‘separate’ only in the
sense that the human mind has to think of them separately (‘two in contemplation
alone’). Nevertheless, he agreed that the differences between the natures are
not annulled by the union, and this was an adequate basis for an accord with
Antioch.222
Cyril’s
acceptance of this formula and of the orthodoxy of the Antiochenes, apart from
Nestorius himself, caused dismay to some of his followers. The reason was that
after writing his Second Letter to Nestorius he had in the meantime adopted a
belligerently miaphysite (one-nature) position: he had come to insist that
Christ is ‘one incarnate nature’, to employ the Johannine affirmation of the
Word becoming flesh with emphasis (while being careful to add that this involved
no change in the divine nature itself), and to attribute all the human
experiences to the divine Son as their one and only personal subject – in
reaction to the Antiochene ascription of the human experiences of Christ to the
human nature treated as a distinct subject of attribution. It was this
difference regarding the identity of the subject in Christ that was the key
factor that set the two schools in opposition to each other. Cyril expressed
his stance in a particularly aggressive form in the Twelve Chapters, or
Anathemas, which he appended to his Third Letter to Nestorius (of November
430):223
Anathema 1.
If anyone does not acknowledge Emmanuel to be God in truth and therefore the
holy Virgin to be Theotokos – for she gave fleshly birth to the flesh that the
Word of God had become –, let him be anathema.
Anathema 12.
If anyone does not acknowledge the Word of God as having suffered in the flesh,
been crucified in the flesh, tasted death in the flesh, and become firstborn
from the dead, since as God he is life and life-giving, let him be anathema.
Dioscorus and
his supporters laid great emphasis on these Anathemas, or Chapters, while
denying authority to the Formula of Reunion. Our view of how Cyrillian is the
Chalcedonian Definition will depend on to which of these two Cyrils – the
moderate Cyril of the Second Letter to Nestorius and the Letter to John of
Antioch, or the uncompromising Cyril of the Twelve Chapters – we give priority.
Cyril at Chalcedon
The fathers
of Chalcedon were profuse in their professions of loyalty to Cyril. Even when
judging the Tome of Pope Leo (the great western Christological statement,
formally approved at Chalcedon), their criterion of orthodoxy remained
agreement with Cyril; this is clear throughout the lengthy discussion of the
Tome in the fourth session.224 Even more revealing was an earlier moment, when in
the second session there occurred a reading of the Tome that was interrupted at
several points by dissentient voices. Some of the bishops present took offence
at the words, ‘[Christ] has from us the humanity that is less than the Father,
and he has from the Father the Godhead that is equal with the Father.’ Theodoret
of Cyrrhus, the champion of the Antiochene party, defended Leo by pointing out,
‘There is a similar instance in the blessed Cyril which contains the words, “He
became man without shedding what was his own, for he remained what he was; he
is certainly conceived as one dwelling in another, that is, the divine nature
in what is human”.’ (II. 26). Nothing could be more indicative of the mood of the
council than the fact that even Theodoret had to defend the Tome by appealing
to the authority of Cyril. His own attitude was far more critical: he had
strongly attacked Cyril’s Twelve Chapters back in the pamphlet war in early 431
and had been very reluctant to accept Nestorius’ subsequent condemnation. But
he clearly recognized that it would be disastrous to argue that there was
something valuable in the Tome of Leo that was lacking in Cyril; instead, he
played along with the conviction of the majority that Cyril provided the
yardstick of orthodoxy. It was as an expression of this conviction that the
Second Letter to Nestorius and the Letter to John of Antioch were read out and
acclaimed at the second session of the Council (II. 18–19), in the place of
honour immediately after the recitation of the creed. These are the two letters
that we have already cited as the key texts of ‘moderate’ Cyrillianism; and
these are the letters of Cyril that are referred to with immense respect as the
‘conciliar letters’ of Cyril in the Chalcedonian Definition itself.
It is to
misconceive the mood of the council to think of the Definition as attempting a
synthesis between Cyril’s theology and that of the Antiochene school. It is to
be noted that the council fathers always refer to the Formula of Reunion as the
‘Letter of Cyril to John of Antioch’: they treat the formula as having become,
by adoption, a Cyrillian text, and accord no credit whatsoever to the
Antiochene school for its production. The way they treated Theodoret in the
eighth session as virtually a repentant heretic is clear evidence that,
although after the quashing of the decrees of Ephesus II they had no choice but
to reinstate him, they were only ready to do so after subjecting him to
personal humiliation. The fathers only accepted from Antioch what they knew
Cyril had not only tolerated but also made his own.225
It would also
be a mistake to interpret the Definition as a synthesis between Alexandria and
Rome. The council solemnly approved the Tome of Leo, and it was as a result of
Roman insistence that the Definition contains an unambiguous statement of two
natures in Christ. There were significant non-Cyrillian features in the
Christology of Leo, as of the west in general; in a word, while Cyril treated
Christ’s human nature as the instrument of the divine Word, Leo emphasized the
cooperation of the two natures in ‘the one mediator between God and men, the
man Christ Jesus’ (1 Tim. 2:5).226 If we take Leo’s Christology as our starting point, a
very different interpretation of the Definition emerges. But this was certainly
not envisaged by the council fathers themselves: they interpreted the Tome as
simply a confirmation of the insistence by the Home Synod of Constantinople of
448, in its condemnation of Eutyches, that Christ is consubstantial both with
the Father and with us men, and that therefore there are two natures in Christ
that remain distinct even after the union (I. 526). The distinctive features of
western Christology echoed in the Tome were of no concern to the council
fathers whatsoever.227 In all, despite the formal approval of the Tome by
the eastern bishops both before the council, at the council, and in the
Definition itself, it remained far less important for them than the conciliar
letters of Cyril.
But what of
the uncompromising Cyril of the Twelve Chapters? During the first session of
the Council of Ephesus of 449 the two conciliar letters were read out in the
course of reading the minutes of the Home Synod of Constantinople of 448 (I.
240, 246). Hereupon Bishop Eustathius of Berytus pointed out to the assembly
that the Letter to John of Antioch needed to be interpreted in the light of the
letters Cyril had written subsequently to his supporters, giving a miaphysite
slant to his acceptance of the Formula of Reunion (I. 261). When this comment
was read out at Chalcedon, the chairman asked the council whether it could be
squared with the two conciliar letters. In an angry response, Eustathius ‘came
forward to the centre, threw down a book and said, “If I have spoken wrongly,
here is the book of Cyril. Let it be anathematized and let me be anathematized”’(I.
265). The effect of Eustathius’ intervention was marred when he proceeded to
adduce the miaphysite sympathies of Flavian of Constantinople, and could then
do nothing but humbly apologize when the chairman asked why he had condemned
Flavian for heresy (I. 267–9). Similarly, after the reading of Leo’s Tome at
the second session Bishop Atticus of Nicopolis argued that the Tome needed to
be compared to the Twelve Chapters (II. 29). In a subsequent informal meeting
of the bishops, the Roman delegates had to satisfy their eastern colleagues by
playing down the dyophysite emphasis in the Tome (IV. 9, after §98), but
nothing more was heard of Cyril’s Chapters or indeed of any other of his
controverted writings.
An analysis of the Definition
To this
emphasis on the Cyril of the Second Letter to Nestorius and the Letter to John
of Antioch I have given the name ‘moderate Cyrillianism’. It is this that
dominates in the Chalcedonian Definition itself, to an analysis of which we may
now turn.228
The final
section of the Definition, as read out at the fifth session of the council,
runs as follows:
Following,
therefore, the holy fathers, we all in harmony teach confession of one and the
same Son our Lord Jesus Christ, the same perfect in Godhead and the same
perfect in manhood, truly God and the same truly man, of a rational soul and body,
consubstantial with the Father in respect of the Godhead, and the same consubstantial
with us in respect of the manhood, like us in all things apart from sin,
begotten from the Father before the ages in respect of the Godhead, and the same
in the last days for us and for our salvation from the Virgin Mary the Theotokos
in respect of the manhood, one and the same Christ, Son, Lord, Onlybegotten, acknowledged
in two natures without confusion, change, division, or separation (the
difference of the natures being in no way destroyed by the union, but rather
the distinctive character of each nature being preserved and coming together into
one person and one hypostasis), not parted or divided into two persons, but one
and the same Son, Only-begotten, God, Word, Lord, Jesus Christ.229
The Christological
model employed here is one that begins with Godhead and humanity as two
distinct natures and then affirms their union in Christ.230
This may seem
an Antiochene emphasis on duality, but that there are two elements in Christ,
distinct but united, was equally affirmed by Cyril himself.231 Typical of
Cyril’s exposition of this model was the use of expressions that shifted the
emphasis onto the oneness in Christ. What in fact we have here is a restatement
of the Formula of Reunion (quoted at p. 64 above) with modifications taken from
Cyril. The Formula’s undeveloped affirmation that ‘there has occurred a union of
two natures, and therefore we acknowledge one Christ, one Son, one Lord’ is
expanded in a way that echoes the following statement in the Second Letter to
Nestorius:
While the
natures which were brought together in true union are different, yet from them
both is the one Christ and Son – not as though the difference of the natures
was destroyed by the union, but rather the Godhead and the manhood by their
ineffable and indescribable coming together into unity perfected for us the one
Lord and Christ and Son.
The language
of ‘coming together into unity’, together with the insistence that this is a
unity of ‘hypostasis’, that is, of concrete, individual existence, gives
conceptual clarity to the insistent repetition of ‘one and the same Son’. Famously,
the clause referring to two natures was redrafted at the last moment to satisfy
the emperor and the Roman delegates, who insisted on a formal affirmation of a
continuing duality in Christ after the union – in accordance with the Home
Synod’s condemnation of Eutyches and with the Tome of Leo. But note that the
clause is so worded as to echo closely a less controversial statement a few
lines above:
We all in
harmony teach confession of one and the same Son our Lord Jesus Christ, the
same perfect IN Godhead and the same perfect IN manhood … one and the same
Christ, Son, Lord, Only-begotten, acknowledged IN two natures. Here the
expression in the Formula of Reunion ‘perfect God and perfect man’ is changed
to ‘perfect in Godhead and the same perfect in manhood’ in accordance with
Cyril’s paraphrase of the Formula in his Letter to John of Antioch; the effect
is to reduce the two natures to two sets of contrasting attributes possessed by
the same subject. The same is implied by the way in which in the key clause,
‘the distinctive character of each nature being preserved and coming together
into one person and one hypostasis’, it is not ‘two natures’ that are said to
be united but the distinctive character, or features, of Godhead and manhood.
The verbal ascription of these attributes to ‘two natures’ has the force of
protecting the two sets from mutual contamination; it is not to be understood
as attributing them to two distinct beings or two subjects of attribution.232
The treatment
of the two natures as two sets of attributes raises the question of whom, then,
if not the natures, is the personal subject in Christ? A set of attributes,
even two sets of attributes taken in conjunction, cannot add up to a personal
subject! The obvious candidate is the ‘one person and one hypostasis’. It is
true that this features in the Definition almost as if it were the product of
the union, with the two natures of Godhead and manhood ‘coming together’ to
form a new compound, but this is simply an accident of the Christological model
employed, that of two elements that join to form a unity: the language of
‘coming together’ arises from a mental analysis of the union, in which we think
of the two constituents separately and then of their union; Cyril used it constantly,
without any intention of casting doubt on the affirmation that the union
consists in the pre-existent divine hypostasis of the Word uniting to himself a
human nature: the one hypostasis for Cyril was not a product but the subject of
the union.233
Clearly the one person and hypostasis is identical to ‘one and the same
Son our Lord Jesus Christ’ who comes in this section of the Definition as the
subject who possesses the two sets of attributes. Is this subject simply
Godhead and manhood existing and acting together, as equal co-partners in the
union, or is it the eternal Word? Now in the second half of this key section of
the Definition the Son is further defined as ‘one and the same Christ, Son,
Lord, Only-begotten … one and the same Son, Only-begotten, God, Word, Lord, Jesus
Christ’. Note here how the Son is defined by some terms that could be applied
to both natures (Christ, Son, Lord) and by some that apply only to the divine
nature (Only-begotten, God, Word), while none of the terms used is specifically
human. This is not, then, a symmetrical definition of the Son, but deliberately
echoes the language of the Nicene Creed, where the subject of the incarnation
and the human experiences is defined as ‘one Lord Jesus Christ the Son of God,
begotten from the Father as only-begotten …, God from God, light from light,
true God from true God, begotten not made, consubstantial with the Father’ –
that is, as specifically God the Word.
In all, the
‘one hypostasis’ of the Definition is indeed the eternal Word – not separated
from the manhood, but the Word incarnate, that is, a personal subject divine in
his own nature and existing from all eternity, who adopted and made his own a second,
human nature and all the qualities and experiences of that nature. The
Definition is indeed based on the Formula of Reunion, originally an Antiochene
document, but it interprets and paraphrases it in strict accordance with what
we have called moderate Cyrillianism.234
Chalcedon’s qualified Cyrillianism
But how would
the other Cyril – the uncompromising Cyril of the Twelve Chapters – have judged
the Definition? In 437, in a letter that accompanied copies of his last major
work, the dialogue That Christ is one, he wrote as follows:
I have
written a short book on the incarnation, summing up the faith under three heads:
the first is that the holy Virgin is Theotokos, the second is that Christ is
one and not two, while the third is that the Word of God, while remaining
incapable of suffering, suffered in his own flesh for us.235
The
Definition certainly affirms Theotokos, and is equally insistent that Christ is
one and not two, but it does not assert explicitly that the subject of the
passion was the eternal Word. Now the Antiochenes had directly attacked ‘theopaschite’
expressions – that is, expressions that attribute the passion on the cross to
the Godhead: they insisted that it was the manhood alone that suffered. While
agreeing with the Antiochenes about the impassibility of the Godhead, Cyril
insisted nonetheless that we must at the same time profess that God the Word is
the one who suffered, albeit not in his own nature but in the human nature he
had made his own; as he wrote in the Third Letter to Nestorius:
We profess
that the very Son begotten of God the Father and Only-begotten God, although in
his own nature he is impassible, suffered in flesh for us according to the
scriptures, and that he was in the crucified body, appropriating impassibly the
sufferings of his own flesh.236
What do we
find in the Definition? On divine impassibility it states that the council
criticizes those ‘fantasizing that the divine nature of the Onlybegotten is
passible’, and ‘it removes from the list of priests those who dare to say that
the Godhead of the Only-begotten is passible’ (V. 34). This was intended to
rebut not Cyril’s defence of theopaschite language but the errors of Eutyches,
who was (unfairly) understood to teach such a merging of the two natures in
Christ that both lost their distinctive properties and the Godhead became as
changeable and vulnerable as his creatures. Nevertheless it is a weakness in
the Definition that it fails to express the paradox that is arguably the heart
and kernel of the mystery of the incarnation.237
It can still
be argued, however, that in the debate between Alexandria and Antioch on the
propriety of theopaschite language the Definition is by implication on the
Alexandrian side. Let us note that in the creeds that are given pride of place
in the text the grammatical subject of ‘suffered’ is ‘Jesus Christ …, God from
God …, consubstantial with the Father’. It was the whole burden of Cyril’s
Second Letter to Nestorius, a text formally approved in the Definition, that
all the human experiences, including the sufferings, are to be ascribed to the
Word of God, and I have argued that this is also the implication of the
Definition’s concluding section. Chalcedon is not to be read as discouraging
theopaschite expressions, but rather as refusing to shove them down everyone’s
throat.
A certain
reserve about theopaschite language was typical of moderate Cyrillianism. This
was not just a position temporarily adopted in the most diplomatic, and
therefore possibly the least sincere, of Cyril’s writings, nor a mere
compromise concocted at Chalcedon, but had become by the time of the council
the dominant theology of the Greek east. This has been illustrated by several
writers from the doctrinal position of Bishop Basil of Seleucia in Isauria, who
deserves particular attention since he was the originator of the expression
adopted by the Definition ‘acknowledged in two natures’.238 When Basil
produced this phrase at the Home Synod of 448 he linked it explicitly to the
teaching of Cyril (I. 301); he even defended qualified miaphysite expressions,
both at Ephesus II (I. 791) and more surprisingly at Chalcedon (I. 176), as equivalent
to the assertion of two natures. Yet his surviving writings avoid theopaschite
language, and in their treatment of the passion lay heavier emphasis on the
impassibility of God than on the fact that the Word made the sufferings his
own. A cautious attitude towards theopaschite expressions could be found within
the Cyrillian camp as well as at Antioch.
In all, the
Definition, through its emphasis on the creed as interpreted by Cyril, implied
that the passion can properly be ascribed to the eternal Son, and yet it
refused to elevate this into a criterion of orthodoxy. In so doing it reflected
a dominant consensus that appealed from Cyril drunk to Cyril sober, from the
Cyril who made enemies to the Cyril who found friends. Of course this moderate
position owed something to the determined and sustained rejection of Cyril’s
Twelve Chapters by the champions of the Antiochene school, but it would be a
mistake to think of the Chalcedonian fathers as themselves consciously
attempting a synthesis between Alexandria and Antioch. They believed they were
being loyal to Cyril.
The broader perspective
In arguing
for the essentially Cyrillian character of the Definition, in accordance with
the best modern studies,239 one may hope to do justice to both the logic of the
Definition and the circumstances of its composition. But to understand the
persistence and inconclusiveness of the subsequent debate over the Definition,
which in the ecumenical context as well as in the world of scholarship
continues to this day, it is equally important to recognize its ambiguities.240
We have seen
how the Definition took as its basis the Formula of Reunion; this was in origin
an Antiochene document, dyophysite in structure as well as in details of
wording. We noted also how, in the final revision, pressures from Rome and the
emperor imposed the inclusion in the Definition of an unambiguously dyophysite
formula (‘in two natures’). The work of the editorial committee in making this
material serve as an expression of Cyrillian Christology was brilliant but
artificial. There is something defective in a conciliar document that requires
such nicety of exegesis as we have attempted above.
The assertion
of two natures and the avoidance of theopaschite expressions were open, as we
have shown, to a perfectly Cyrillian interpretation. But the fact that they
were accompanied in the work of the council by the condemnation of Dioscorus
and reinstatement of Theodoret (and his controversial ally Ibas) gave
plausibility to the charge that the Definition, while pretending to honour
Cyril, had in fact betrayed him.241 It is this that led immediately after the council to
determined opposition in some parts of the east, and eventually to the schism
between the rest of the church and the churches variously called ‘Monophysite’
(a pejorative term, best avoided), ‘miaphysite’, ‘Oriental Orthodox’, or simply
‘non-Chalcedonian’.242 Meanwhile, while the bishops of Chalcedon interpreted
Leo’s Tome according to the teaching of Cyril, western theologians down the
centuries have read the Definition in the light of the teaching of Leo and of
western Christology generally; despite their common loyalty to the Chalcedonian
formula, more divides Eastern Orthodox Christology from the main current of
western Christology than from that of the miaphysite churches. None of these various
readings of the Definition is simply erroneous, since all can be traced back to
voices within the council itself. The great majority of the council fathers who
signed the text assured themselves (as is clear from the Codex Encyclius) that
it did no more than expound the obvious meaning of the Nicene Creed in terms
indebted to Cyril of Alexandria; but history was to show that the Chalcedonian
Definition had opened a Pandora’s box.
(Acts of Chalcedon, Richard Price, pp.
56-74)
201 On the
development of miaphysite Christian churches and cultural traditions in lands beyond
the borders of the eastern empire, see Fowden 1993, 100–37. On the evolution of
the various Chalcedonian and non-Chalcedonian churches in the east, see Binns
2002.
202 For the
crucial importance of the Nicene Creed both at Chalcedon and in the preceding stages
of the controversy, see de Halleux 1985.
203 He was also
firmly anti-Eutychian; see Lebon 1908, 685–6.
204 ACO 2.5 pp.
24–98. For a full analysis, see Grillmeier 1987, 195–235.
205 This canon,
adopted on 22 July 431, comes in the minutes of Session I of Chalcedon (I. 945).
206 ACO 2.5 p.
33.
207 Note that the
final paragraph of the Definition, insisting that ‘no one is allowed to produce
or compose or construct another creed or to think or teach otherwise’, is a
reaffirmation of the definitive status of the Nicene Creed, not a reference to
the Definition itself.
208 A credal recitation
was standard at baptism from at least the second century. The adoption of the
creed into the eucharistic liturgy was a post-Chalcedonian development (Dix 1945,
485–8), but expressed a sense of the link between communion and belief that was
traditional.
209 The best
treatments in English are Young 1983, 178–289, and Grillmeier 1975, 414–519.
For a caution over talk of two ‘schools’ see Gavrilyuk 2004, 137–9.
210 This is
illustrated in the collection of excerpts from Nestorius given in the Acts at I.
944.
211 For ‘nature’,
‘hypostasis’ and ‘person’, see Glossary, vol. 3, 207–10.
212 See Russell
2000, esp. 3–63, and 2004, 191–205.
213 ‘One after
the union’ balanced ‘two before the union’ – expressions that were not intended
in a temporal sense, as if the two natures existed in separation before the
union and then came together, but in a logical one: only if we mentally set
aside the union does Christ appear as two, while in reality Christ is a single
being.
214 Theodore of
Mopsuestia, Commentario al Vangelo di Giovanni, 209–10.
215 Cyril of
Alexandria, Commentary on the Gospel of John, PG 74. 96 AB.
216 See the
important summary of Antiochene doctrine in the expanded paraphrase of the
creed attributed to Theodore of Mopsuestia and used by Nestorius’ agents in
Asia Minor (I. 921).
217 Cyril,
Defence of the Twelve Chapters against Theodoret, PG 76. 416C.
218 It remains a
weakness that Cyril invokes kenôsis when interpreting specific gospel
testimonies to human limitations in Christ but tends in most contexts to treat
Christ’s humanity as ‘deified’, that is, so taken up by the Godhead as to enjoy
divine powers. The difference between the earthly Christ and the heavenly,
ascended Christ is constantly blurred.
219 See Lampe,
PGL, 639. Bishop John of Antioch, a critical ally of Nestorius, pointed this
out to him, ep. 4, ACO 1.1.1 p. 95. 19–20.
220 The full text
is in the Acts of Chalcedon, I. 240.
221 For the full
text, see I. 246. I omit the final sentence on the distribution of the sayings
between the two natures, for this could not really be squared with Cyril’s
theology and was accordingly omitted in the paraphrase of the Formula
incorporated into the Chalcedonian Definition.
222 See de
Halleux 1993a.
223 Cyril of
Alexandria, Select Letters, 28–33.
224 See Diepen
1953, 74.
225 Contrast
Chadwick 1983, 12, ‘The Council of Chalcedon protected the droit de cité of
Antiochene Christology’, and de Halleux 1990b, 52, Chalcedon ‘guaranteed the
values of the “Antiochene” view of Christology’. It could be argued that this
was implied by the Definition’s Dyophysite language, but it was not the
intention of the council fathers, nor was it the actual fruit of the council
after the debates of the sixth century. For the lack of Antiochene sympathies
in the members of the committee that produced the final form of the Definition,
see our commentary on Session V (vol. 2, 188–9).
226 For Leo’s
Christology, see Grillmeier 1975, 526–39, and 1987, 149–72; Sellers 1953,
228-53; Studer 1985; Mühlenberg 1997, 14–16.
227 This was due
not merely to Greek indifference towards western theology but to the
deficiencies of the Tome itself, which was a contribution to rhetoric rather
than theology. Not until the Monoenergist and Monothelete controversies of the
seventh century did it make any positive contribution to theological
understanding.
228 The main
points in the following discussion accord with those of Norris 1996, 140–7.
229 V. 34. For
the stages in the drafting of the Definition, see our commentary on the fifth
session, vol. 2, 184–90.
230 Note that the
attributes that define the two natures include individualizing notes (such as
begotten of the Father and born of Mary) as well as generic ones. Later Greek
theology treated the two natures as generic and attributed all the
individualizing notes to the one hypostasis; this changed the meaning of the
Chalcedonian formula.
231 For a correct
understanding of the Definition, it is crucial to realize that Cyril used the
‘composition’ model of two elements that make up the one Christ as well as the
‘narrative’ or ‘kenotic’ model of the divine Word who emptied himself to become
flesh. See Norris 1975.
232 This
interpretation agrees with that in the Assurance issued by Cyrus of Alexandria
in 633, ‘The same [Christ] is perfect in Godhead and perfect in manhood, and is
discerned in two natures in this respect alone’ (ACO, Ser. 2, vol. 2,
598.16–18). Unfortunately the expression ‘two natures’ was widely used at the
time of Chalcedon to express a less nuanced Dyophysitism; this naturally led
many Cyrillians to criticize Chalcedon’s adoption of the expression.
233 In the west,
however, this clause of the Definition, which derives with modifications from
Leo’s Tome, was understood in the opposite sense. ‘For Leo the one person is
not the point of origin but the result of the union’ (Studer 1985, 454).
234 Our analysis
may seem to do less than justice to what was new at Chalcedon: ‘The Chalcedonian
Definition is a landmark in the history of Christian thought by reason of its distinction
between nature and person’ (Chadwick 1983, 11). In applying ‘nature’ to the
duality in Christ and ‘person and hypostasis’ to the unity, Chalcedon paved the
way for developments in the sixth century when the meaning of these terms was
exhaustively analysed, but since in the Definition itself they were vague and
undefined it cannot be said that the council itself marked any advance in
Christological understanding; nor did it claim to.
235 Ep. 64, ACO
1.4 p. 229 (Collectio Casinensis 299); see Cyril of Alexandria, Deux dialogues christologiques,
75–8. Note the falsity of the oft-repeated assertion that Cyril moderated his
language and effectively dropped the Chapters after agreeing to the Formula of Reunion.
236 Cyril of
Alexandria, Select Letters, 20.
237 This
criticism was forcibly made by Severus of Antioch, Homiliae Cathedrales 1.12–25,
PO 38, 260–7. For the importance of the theopaschite issue, see O’Keefe 1997a
and 1997b.
238 For Basil’s
Christology, see van Parys 1971 and Martzelos 1994. For the meaning of ‘acknowledged
in two natures’ see vol. 2, 189, n. 15.
239 The
outstanding analysis of the text and its sources is de Halleux 1976. De Halleux
1994 is sharply critical of an attempt by Martzelos 1986 to read the full
Cyrillian position into Chalcedon, but agrees that ‘Catholic and Protestant historiography
of the dogma tends nowadays to recognize the Cyrillian character of the
Definition’ (pp. 468–9). The dominance of the Cyrillian reading of the
Definition in current scholarship is confirmed by Wendebourg 1997, 208. But
some scholars still see the council as a defeat for Cyrillian Christology, e.g.
Mühlenberg 1997.
240 For recent
ecumenical dialogue between Oriental Orthodox, Eastern Orthodox and western
Christians, centred on problems arising from Chalcedon, see Gregorios et al.
1981; de Halleux 1991; Kirchschläger and Stirnemann 1992; Wendebourg 1997; Olmi
2003.
241 The simple
fact that the Definition used a ‘two nature’ formula damned it in the eyes of the
allies and followers of Dioscorus, quite apart from any other consideration.
242 ‘Non-Chalcedonian’
to designate the miaphysites ignores the existence of the Dyophysite
non-Chalcedonian tradition maintained in the Assyrian Church or ‘Church of the East’
(the ancient Church of Persia), which has never accepted the condemnation of
Nestorius.
No comments:
Post a Comment