Theological
Issues Involved in the Filioque
Paul
D. Molnar
Rather
than a historical discussion of the problems associated with the filioque, this
will be an exploration of its theological implications.1 Most would agree that the phrase stating that
the Spirit proceeds from the Father and the Son was unecumenically added to the
Creed by the Western Church.2 Many
also would agree that the original intention of this statement underscores the
belief of both East and West that the Holy Spirit is homoousion with the Father
and the Son, that is, the Spirit is worshipped and glorified together with the
Father and Son as one God in three persons. Karl Barth, for instance, believed
that from the beginning East and West did not disagree materially about the
procession of the Spirit even when the expression was used, and he maintained
that passages such as Jn 15.26, which speak of the Spirit proceeding from the
Father, could not be isolated from other New Testament texts that clearly refer
to the Spirit of the Son. Thus, he explicitly affirmed the filioque because he
held that
statements about the divine modes of
being antecedently in themselves cannot be different in content from those that
are to be made about their reality in revelation. All our statements concerning
what is called the immanent Trinity.3
Thomas
F. Torrance also noted that this was its original intention and partially
agreed with Barth, even though, as we shall see below, he had reservations
about the ‘ element of “subordinationism” in his doctrine of the Trinity’,
which he believed was a ‘hang-over from Latin theology but also from St Basil’s
doctrine of the Trinity’.4 As we
shall see, Torrance held that if theologians returned to the thinking of
Athanasius and Cyril,5 then the
problem of subordinationism within the immanent Trinity would not even arise
and there would be no need for the filioque since all would agree that Father,
Son and Spirit are each fully divine and inseparably equal in being, in virtue
of their perichoretic or co-inherent eternal relations. At stake ultimately is
the unity of the Trinity.
Before
we get ahead of ourselves, however, it might be worth noting that the issue of
the filioque is one that is ripe for true ecumenical agreement today among the
Orthodox, Anglicans, Lutherans, Roman Catholics and Reformed. Avery Dulles, for
instance, relying heavily on the thinking of Yves Congar, points out that in
the East, Maximus the Confessor had no difficulty accepting the filioque when
rightly understood.6 And that meant
that it could not imply that there were two ultimate sources of the Spirit
within the Godhead. Such a notion would undermine the unity of the Trinity on a
very basic level since if there were two ultimate sources for the Spirit, one
of them would have to be inferior to the other. And that is precisely what the Nicene
view of the Trinitarian relations rightly rejected. After considering the
historical and theological developments surrounding the filioque, Dulles favored
retaining the filioque for various reasons. Yet he also seemed open to
accepting both the Eastern and Western formulations, namely, that the Spirit
proceeds ‘from the Father through the Son’ and that the Spirit ‘ proceeds from
the Father and the Son’ as long as these two expressions are seen as
complementary rather than as contradictory7
and as long as both expressions are rightly understood.
Yves
Congar was more daring since he proposed that the Western Church should
suppress the filioque today because we now have ‘an atmosphere which recognizes
that two different expressions of a common faith may be compatible and
equivalent to each other’8 and such
suppression ‘would be a gesture of humility and brotherhood on the part of the
Roman Catholic Church which might have wide-reaching ecumenical implications’.9 But, in his view, two conditions must be met.
First, the two expressions should follow the agreed path followed at the
Council of Florence which held that they were complementary expressions of the
same faith. That means that ‘ the non-heretical character of the Filioque,
properly understood’ must be affirmed and that the depth of the Eastern
tradition should be respected as long as the Orthodox do not ‘go beyond the
implications in the “from the Father alone” of the monarchy of the Father and
the demands made by the New Testament texts’.10
Second, Christians on both sides should be prepared for this ‘so that it may be
done in the light, in patience, with respect for each other’s legitimate
sensibilities and in love’.11
What
is notable about these suggestions is that they open the door to much wider
theological agreement because in part they are quite similar to the suggestions
offered by T. F. Torrance who was instrumental in formulating the agreed statement
on the Trinity in 199112 between the
Reformed and Eastern Orthodox churches. As indicated above, Torrance believed
that once the element of subordinationism within the Trinity was set aside by
firmly asserting the full equality of the three persons as the one God of
Christian faith, then there could be no question as to whether or not there was
more than one principle of origin of the Spirit, because the Spirit would be
understood to proceed from the being of the Father and not from the person of
the Father in the sense that the Father was the cause of the being either of
the Son or of the Spirit. Hence, Torrance himself concluded that both sides
could affirm that the Spirit proceeds ‘ from the Father through the Son’ and ‘
from the Father and the Son’ as long as the full equality of the three persons
in the one being of God was maintained.13
But,
like Congar, he also had his conditions. One could only accept both of these
statements as long as they are not understood to mean: (1) ‘ that the Monarchy
is limited to the Father which both the Western and the Eastern Church have
held in their different ways’; (2) ‘ that there is a distinction between the
underived Deity of the Father and the derived Deity of the Son and Spirit’ and
(3) ‘ that the Holy Spirit does not belong equally and completely homoousially
with the Father and the Son in their two-way relation within one another in the
divine Triunity’.14 In other words as
long as the monarchy or the fullness of divinity is not lodged in the Father
alone as Person, there would be no possibility of espousing the idea that the
Father is the cause of the divinity of the Son and of the Spirit. And as long
as the monarchy of God is lodged within the perichoretic relations of the
Trinitarian persons, the idea that there could be two ultimate principles that
might be the source of the Spirit would never even arise as a possibility.
Moreover, Torrance wanted to stress that the formula ‘ one Being, three
Persons’ had to be understood in a completely personal way to avoid any idea
that the one being of God that is common to all three Persons is not personal. Such
an idea would rest on a preconceived idea of divine unity and therefore would
not be derived from God’s self-revelation in Jesus Christ and through the
Spirit. It would thus obscure the fact that ‘the “One Being” of God does not
refer to some abstract divine essence, but to the intrinsically personal “I am”
of God’.15
While
neither Dulles nor Congar ever referred to the agreed statement between the
Reformed and the Orthodox, it still remains true that both Dulles and Congar on
the Roman Catholic side and Torrance on the Reformed side reached very similar
conclusions even though the problem of inadvertently espousing the idea of a ‘derived
deity’ and Torrance’s emphasis on the personal nature of the divine being might
require further ecumenical discussion. Still, these agreements would seem to be
extremely promising from an ecumenical perspective. In the rest of this chapter
I would like to explore more deeply the theological issues embedded in the
filioque by discussing in some depth the reasons why Torrance criticized what
he took to be an element of subordinationism in Barth’s doctrine of the Trinity
along with a recent proposed solution that relies on Torrance and Barth in
order to see whether or not the suggestions of Congar and Dulles on the one side
and Torrance on the other could form the basis of a very practical agreement
among the Christian churches.
I. Torrance and the element of
subordinationism in Barth’s doctrine of the Trinity
What
exactly was Torrance referring to when he spoke of his ‘chief difference with
Barth’ with respect to the earlier volumes of the Church Dogmatics? As seen
above, Torrance himself says that this difference concerned ‘the element of
“subordinationism” in his doctrine of the Holy Trinity’ which he considered a
‘hang-over from Latin theology but also from St Basil’s doctrine of the
Trinity’.16 He believed that Barth’s
support of the Latin text of the Creed was precisely what left him with that
element of ‘subordinationism’. Torrance thought that this influenced his approach
to the filioque clause in the Western version of the Nicene Creed. He
completely agreed with Barth’s view that the homoousion applied to the Holy
Spirit so that the historical mission of the Spirit had to be traced back ‘from
the incarnate Son to the eternal mission of the Spirit from the Father’. But,
in Torrance’s view, the very problem of the filioque ‘ was created by an
incipient subordinationism in the Cappadocian doctrine of the Trinity, which
the Eastern Church had to answer in one way and the Western Church in another
way’.17 His position was that
Athanasius, Gregory Nazianzen and Cyril of Alexandria all ‘ rejected
subordinationism in Trinitarian relations’ and if we followed their thinking,
the whole issue that led to the filioque never would have arisen in the first
place and there would have been no reason for division between East and West.
He believes that if we return to their approach then ‘ the unecumenical Western
intrusion of the filioque clause into the Nicene-Constantinopolitan Creed simply
falls away’.18 Moreover, according to
Torrance, Gregory Nazianzen not only influenced both Calvin and Barth, but ‘
had expressed some serious misgivings with respect to the teaching of his
fellow Cappadocians Basil and his brother Gregory’.19
The
crucial issue here concerns the idea of causality. Torrance held that the
Cappadocians ‘ were tempted to account for the oneness and threeness of God
through recourse to the dangerous analogy of three different people having a
common nature’ and that left them open to the charge of tritheism which they
strongly rejected.20 But, according
to Torrance, they attempted to preserve God’s oneness by claiming that
God the Father, who is himself without
generation or origination, is the one Principle or Origin (ἀρχή) and Cause
(αἰτία) of the Son and the Spirit, although in such a way that there is no
interval of existence, time or space between them and no “before” or “after” in
the order of their being.21
Their
notion of cause was unique in that it consisted of and was continuous with its
effects. Gregory Nyssen spoke of the Son and Spirit being caused not in their
nature but with respect to their ‘mode of existence’. Yet, ‘ he thought of the
being of Holy Spirit as grounded through the being of the Son in the being of
the Father’.22 At this point Torrance
notes a twofold problem in the way Gregory Nyssen presents the procession of
the Spirit. These are the words of Gregory:
The Holy Spirit, from whom the supply
of all good things in the creation has its source, is attached to the Son with
whom he is inseparably apprehended. He depends for his being on the Father as
Cause, from whom he also proceeds. It is the identifying mark of his hypostatic
nature that he is known after and with the Son, and that he derives his subsistence
from the Father.23
In
Torrance’s judgement this statement suggests that the Cappadocians’ response to
the charge of tritheism and their effort to maintain the oneness of the Godhead
by referring the three Persons to a
single Principle (ἀρχή) or Cause (αἰτία) in the Father, were made at the
expense of a damaging distinction between the Deity of the Father as wholly
underived or “uncaused”, and the Deity of the Son and of the Spirit as
eternally derived or “caused”.24
In
addition, when they differentiated the Trinitarian Persons ‘ they cast the
internal relations between the Father, the Son and the Holy Spirit into the
consecutive structure of a causal series or a “chain” of dependence “through
the Son”’.25
What
they should have done is conceptualize the Persons more as Athanasius and
Gregory Nazianzen, following Athanasius, had done. Instead of focusing on
causality, they should have focused on the ‘living will of God’ (Athanasius) or
‘the identity of being, movement and will in God’ (Gregory Nazianzen).26 What Torrance finds helpful in the thought of
Gregory Nazianzen is the fact that he stressed that God’s unity was ‘complete
not primarily in the Father but in each Person as well as in all of them’.27 This is the key insight of Athanasius. And while
Gregory Nazianzen also used causal language when referring to the Son and
Spirit and referred to the Father as ἀρχή, he was, according to Torrance, also
aware of the difficulties in that language in that it could imply that the
Father is greater and that the Son and Spirit could be thought of as inferior
to the Father as first principle. This would ‘insult ’ the Father with ‘ the
idea of precedence in honour . . . For there is no greater or less in respect
of the being of the consubstantial Persons . . . To subordinate any of the
three is to overthrow the Trinity’.28
Ultimately, Gregory Nazianzen thought of the Persons as relations ‘ subsisting
in God which are beyond all time . . . beyond all origin ..., and beyond all
cause’.29 Cyril of Alexandria later
took up this idea of the divine relations while specifically rejecting any idea
of causality within the Trinity.30
There
were additional complications. Gregory Nyssen attempted to address the question
of whether or not the being and existence of the Son and Spirit were to be
traced back to the person of the Father. His solution was ambiguous because on
the one hand he claimed that the word God signifies being and not person. This
would imply that ‘ the Father is not God in virtue of his Fatherhood but in
virtue of his being; otherwise neither the Son nor the Holy Spirit would be
God’.31 On the other hand he
simultaneously argued that everything ‘ proceeds from the Father as the centre
of unity, who is properly called “God” for it is in his ὑπόστασις that the ἀρχή
of Deity is lodged’.32 In the end
this suggests that the Son and Spirit do not derive their deity from the Father
but ‘ only their Persons’ or ‘their distinctive modes of existence . . . for
the όὐσία of Deity is one and the same in all’.33
In that sense the Son and Spirit can be considered as ‘ derived from and
causally dependent on the ὑπόστασις or πρόσωπον of the Father’.34 Whereas the term Father was classically used
to refer both to the Godhead of God and to the Person of the Father within the
Trinity without separating these two senses, the Cappadocians completely
conflated these two senses in which God is Father into one and left the Church
with the problem ‘ as to the significance of the Fatherhood of God, and as to
the oneness of the Trinity’.35 This
is a big enough problem.
But
there was an additional difficulty – they also shifted the emphasis from the
homoousios ‘ as the key to the identity, intrinsic oneness, and internal
relations of the Holy Trinity, to emphasis upon the three diverse ὑποστάσeις as
united through the Μοναρχία of the Father and through having one being in
common’.36 All of this weakened
Athanasius’ idea that ‘whatever we say of the Father we say of the Son and the
Spirit except “Father”’.37 According
to Torrance, for Athanasius and for Alexander any idea that the Father alone
was ἀρχή in this sense ‘ was an Arian concept’.38
Athanasius’ view that ‘ the whole Godhead is in the Son and in the Spirit ’ so
that ‘ they must be included with the Father in the one originless ἀρχή of the
Holy Trinity’ is to be preferred.39
In Torrance’s view then even though the Cappadocian stress on the one being,
three persons of the Trinity helped Christians come to a better view of the
distinctive modes of existence of the persons, it discounted the real meaning
of ‘ όὺσία as being in its internal relations’ and robbed ‘οὺσία of its
profound personal sense which was so prominent at Nicaea’.40
II. Barth and the element of
subordinationism
With
this material in place, perhaps we can understand better what Torrance might
have meant when he spoke of the element of ‘subordinationism’ in Barth’s
doctrine of the Trinity. He certainly would have agreed with Barth’s
description of Jesus’ Sonship. But he would have objected to the way Barth
distinguished God the Reconciler from God the Creator even in CD I.1 as Barth
spoke of Father/Son relation in terms of super- and subordination. Thus, on the
one hand, Barth clearly wished to ascribe subordination to Jesus the Son acting
as God the Reconciler for us (i.e., an economic subordination with which
Torrance would agree) as when he explained that it was in the light of the
unity of content of revelation and the
person of the Revealer that we then understood the original and proper sense of
the fatherhood of God: He is Father because he is the Father of this His
only-begotten Son. From the same unity we at once have the further result of
the divine sonship of Jesus Christ. There is no abstract person of the
Revealer, but the person of the Revealer is the person of Jesus Christ who is
subordinate to the Creator revealed by it, yet who is also indissolubly
co-ordinate with Him, who is with Him; in this person the revelation is a
reality. . . there is no Jesus perse who might then acquire also the predicate
of a bearer of the revelation of his Father. Nor is there any revelation of the
Father per se which might then be apprehended in Jesus in an exemplary and
pre-eminent fashion. Jesus is the revelation of the Father and the revelation
of the Father is Jesus. And precisely in virtue of this “is” He is the Son or
Word of the Father. (I.1, p. 412)41
Barth
goes on to explain that there is an order between creation and reconciliation
and that the latter follows and does not precede the former while it is through
the latter that we understand God the Creator and through the former that we
perceive the Reconciler. He says we must distinguish these two ‘in such a way
that we perceive and acknowledge the relation of subordination that is present
here’ (I.1, p. 413). This means that ‘the Reconciler is not the Creator, and
that as the Reconciler He follows the Creator, that He accomplishes, as it
were, a second divine act – not an act which we can deduce from the first,
whose sequence from the first we can survey and see to be necessary, but still
a second act which for all its newness and inconceivability is related to the
first ’ (I.1, p. 413). In other words God is first the Father in heaven who
creates and then in a free act the incarnate Son who reconciles us to himself. There
is therefore an order of creation and reconciliation. To this order, on the
other hand, Barth then claims that
there corresponds christologically the
order of Father and Son or Father and Word. Jesus Christ as the Reconciler
cannot precede the Creator, “our Father in heaven”. He stands to Him in the
irreversible relation of following on Him and from Him as the son follows on
the father. . . . But again this subordination and sequence cannot imply any
distinction of being; it can only signify a distinction in the mode of being...
Here, then, sonship as well as fatherhood, in and with the super- and
subordination expressed thereby, is to be understood as unrestrictedly true
deity. (I.1, pp. 413–14, emphasis mine)42
In
light of what was said above, I think one can easily see that there is some
ambiguity in this particular expression of the matter in the sense that Barth
does not clearly and consistently indicate that the subordination of Jesus the
incarnate Son, the Reconciler, to the Father is an act of economic
condescension for our sakes and not a subordination within the Father/Son
relation. This seems to be exactly what Torrance was objecting to in the
reasoning of the Cappadocians discussed above. To put this in Torrance’s words:
‘the subjection of Christ to the Father in his incarnate economy as the
suffering and obedient Servant cannot be read back into the eternal hypostatic
relations and distinctions subsisting in the Holy Trinity’.43 Here one must distinguish clearly between the
order of the persons within the Trinity and their being – the Father is first
in order – but Father, Son and Spirit
eternally coexist as three fully
co-equal Persons in a perichoretic togetherness and in-each-otherness in such a
way that, in accordance with the particular aspect of divine revelation and
salvation immediately in view, as in the New Testament Scriptures, there may be
an appropriate variation in the trinitarian order from that given in Baptism.44
Nonetheless,
according to Torrance, ‘ both Athanasius and Basil counselled the Church to
keep to the order of the divine Persons given in Holy Baptism, if only to
counter the damaging heresy of Sabellianism’.45
The
additional problem here is that any confounding of the order of the persons
within the immanent Trinity with their co-equal being will necessarily result
in some form of subordination, which will inadvertently lead to a weakening of
the divine unity and thus the co-equality of the persons that both Barth and
Torrance tirelessly sought to uphold. Moreover, it will open the door for a
perceived need for the filioque, which Torrance claims never would have
happened if the full co-equality of the persons of the Trinity were upheld in
the strong Athanasian sense. That then is the issue that arises when one inadvertently
reads back elements of the economy into the immanent Trinity. It may seem like
a minor point, but it has wide-ranging implications because whenever that
happens, God’s eternal being and action are made to be dependent upon his
relations with the world in some way and to that extent his free love becomes
indistinguishable from our human love. I do not believe that Barth himself drew
this conclusion. But a number of his followers certainly have.46 Once that conclusion is drawn, however, it is
only a short move to the kind of thinking that equates love of neighbour with
love of God and leads to arguments like those of John Hick who claims that the
Golden Rule is all that is necessary for all religions because we are all
called to treat others as we would have them treat us. He then claims that it
is unnecessary and incorrect to assert that salvation can come only in and
through Jesus himself.47
This
reading of subordination back into the immanent Trinity becomes even more
explicit in CD IV.1 precisely because Barth carries his confusion of the order
of the persons with their being to their logical conclusion by introducing a
prius and a posterius as well as a superiority and subordination into the
immanent Trinity as a condition for the possibility of the actions ad extra of
the Son and Spirit. Both Torrance and Barth think of the obedience of the Son
as God’s condescension to a life of humble obedience for our benefit. Thus both
of them speak of the incarnate Son as the judge judged in our place,48 and both utterly reject any idea that God is
in conflict with himself in acting for us, as well as any sort of modalism and
subordinationism within the being of God or any idea that God changes in acting
for us either. But, Barth goes beyond this to argue that the basis for what the
incarnate Son does for us is to be found in the obedience and subordination of
the Son within the immanent Trinity.
Barth
did of course mention that it is a difficult and tricky or elusive thing to
speak about an ‘obedience that takes place in God himself’ (IV.1, p. 195). Even
so, he argues that ‘ obedience implies an above and a below, a prius [before]
and a posterius [after], a superior and a junior and subordinate’; indeed,
Barth insists that ‘ a below, a posterius, a subordination ... belongs to the
inner life of God’ (IV.1, p. 201). Barth then asks whether or not these ideas
compromise the unity and equality of the divine being, wondering how God can be
one and also ‘above and below, the superior and the subordinate ’ (IV.1, p.
195) and whether or not such thinking might invite the idea of two divine
beings, one of which is not properly divine at all because he exists only
within creation. Of course he opposes any such thinking. The question here,
however, is this: why does Barth think he must introduce superiority and
subordination into God’s inner life, as when he goes on to say that ‘ a below,
a posterius, a subordination ... belongs to the inner life of God’ (IV.1, p.
201) to make the same point that Torrance makes? That point of course is that
God acts as man in the incarnation so that God suffers both as God and as man
for us in order to destroy sin, suffering, evil and death. But Torrance also
thoroughly rejects any attempt to introduce superiority and subordination into
the immanent Trinity. Both theologians of course firmly rejected the modalist
idea that God the Father suffers eternally even while they accepted that there
was an element of truth in the erroneous position of Patripassianism.49 In CD I.1 Barth also wrote that ‘If
revelation is to be taken seriously as God’s presence, if there is to be a
valid belief in revelation, then in no sense can Christ and the Spirit be
subordinate hypostases’ (I.1, p. 353, emphasis mine). With Barth, Torrance
believes that what God is toward us, he is in himself, and also holds firmly to
the fact that there is no God behind the back of Jesus Christ; both also insist
that the incarnate life of Jesus falls within the being of the eternal Trinity.
But never once does Torrance attempt to ground these assertions in a
superiority and subordination within the immanent Trinity; nor does he claim
there is a prius or a posterius in God’s inner being.50 In fact, following Calvin, Torrance writes:
the principium of the Father does not
import an ontological priority, or some prius aut posterius in God, but has to
do only with a “form of order” (ratio ordinis) or “arrangement” (dispositio) of
inner trinitarian relations governed by the Father/Son relationship, which in
the nature of the case is irreversible, together with the relationship of the
Father and the Son to the Spirit who is the Spirit of the Father and the Spirit
of the Son.51
Consequently,
Torrance firmly and consistently argues that ‘ the subordination of Christ to
the Father in his incarnate and saving economy cannot be read back into the
eternal personal relations and distinctions subsisting in the Holy Trinity’.52
A
full treatment of this matter cannot be presented here.53 But it is worth noting two statements made by
Barth that lead more to confusion than to clarity. These are statements
Torrance expressly avoids because he does not ascribe the Monarchy to the
person of the Father but rather to the being of the Father which is also the
being of the Son and Spirit; therefore Torrance consistently avoids any notion
at all that the Son and Spirit derive their deity from the Father. Furthermore,
Torrance consistently emphasizes the doctrine of perichoresis at precisely this
point and so avoids confusing the order of the Persons with their unity of
being.
First,
speaking of God’s pre-temporal election in relation to Jesus’ human existence
Barth claims that ‘In this free act of the election of grace the Son of the
Father is no longer just the eternal Logos, but as such, as very God from all
eternity He is also the very God and very man He will become in time’ (IV.1, p.
66). How can God already be God and man before he becomes man in time? While
Barth clearly meant to distinguish God’s predestination of himself to be born
of the Virgin for our salvation and affirmed that that event would occur in the
fullness of time, he has unfortunately been read as collapsing the inner
Trinitarian relations (the processions) into the missions. If he had done so,
that would be a clear indication that he had indeed conceptually reduced God to
who and what God is for us in his missions.
He
certainly did not do that when he asserted that to speak of the Son’s being
begotten of the Father before all time means that the pre-existent Son who
exists as God for us by virtue of the incarnation ‘ did not come into being in
an event within the created world’ (I.1, p. 426). Indeed,
Jesus Christ does not first become
God’s Son when He is it for us. He becomes it from eternity; He becomes it as
the eternal Son of the eternal Father. . . . But this becoming (because it is
this becoming) rules out every need of this being for completion. Indeed, this
becoming simply confirms the perfection of this being. (I.1, p. 427)54
That
is why Barth could and did say that
We can certainly say that we see the
love of God to man originally grounded upon the eternal relation of God, Father
and Son. But as this love is already free and unconstrained in God Himself, so,
too, and only then rightly, is it free in its realisation towards man. That is,
in His Word becoming flesh, God acts with inward freedom and not in fulfilment
of a law to which He is supposedly subject. His Word will still be His Word
apart from this becoming, just as Father, Son and Holy Spirit would be none the
less eternal God, if no world had been created. (I.2, p. 135 emphases mine)
And
that is something that he theoretically maintained throughout his career. It is
certainly something Torrance consistently maintained in the interest of
affirming the sovereignty of God’s grace and judgement. For instance, Torrance
insisted that ‘ the incarnation was not a timeless event like the generation of
the Son from the Being of the Father’.55
This is a complex issue as there are times when Barth is very clear in making
such distinctions, as when he says: ‘ Jesus Christ was at the beginning. He was
not at the beginning of God, for God has indeed no beginning. But He was at the
beginning of all things, at the beginning of God’s dealings with the reality
which is distinct from Himself. . . He was the election of God’s grace as
directed towards man’ (II.2, p. 102).56
Second,
Barth claims that ‘In His mode of being as the Son He fulfils the divine
subordination, just as the Father in His mode of being as the Father fulfils
the divine superiority’ (IV.1, p. 209).57
This too is a confusing remark because the eternal persons within the being of
God do not need to fulfil anything even according to Barth’s own understanding
of the Trinity. The only way this statement could make sense is if Barth clearly
had stated at this point that what the Son fulfils in his mission is the
eternal divine decree to be God for us and thus to act as our Reconciler. To
assert simply that the Son fulfils his subordination and that the Father
fulfils his superiority within the immanent Trinity inadvertently implies that
God needs some sort of fulfilment which perhaps then is finally realized in his
actions within history for us. That is something that Barth firmly rejected as
when he wrote: ‘In order to not be alone, single, enclosed within Himself, God
did not need co-existence with the creature. . . . Without the creature He has
all this originally in Himself’ (IV.1, p. 201).58
But it is certainly a road taken by all too many of his followers as already
noted above!
III Understanding the divine Monarchy:
T. F. Torrance and the current discussion
My
intention has been to show that the issues related to the filioque do not stand
in isolation but involve many theological concerns, especially as these have
been contrasted in the thinking of Barth and Torrance. Now I will illustrate
exactly how these problems are still very much in evidence in the thinking of
those who inadvertently introduce some notion of causality into the Father/Son
relation.
A
recent article discussing Torrance’s view of the divine Monarchy does a largely
admirable job duly stressing his emphasis on the twofold meaning of God’s
Fatherhood as noted above. But when the author turns to Karl Barth’s
understanding of these matters, the critical issues raised by Torrance himself
to Barth are glossed over, even though Torrance’s objection to the element of
subordination in Barth’s doctrine of the Trinity is noted in a footnote. The
question about whether or not Barth has illegitimately read back elements of
the economy into the immanent Trinity is not addressed, though the author claims
that Barth’s account of ‘the Father’s property of mastery and the Son’s
property of service’ is better than Torrance’s account.59 He maintains that Torrance simply avoids the
question concerning the Son’s obedience and the Father’s superiority. But the
fact is that Torrance does not avoid this question at all. As already
illustrated, he firmly rejects any idea of ascribing superiority or
subordination to the eternal Trinitarian persons in the interest of avoiding
modalism and subordinationism and in the interest of recognizing the freedom of
grace. The point to be made here, however, is simply this – whenever
subordination is introduced into the immanent Trinity, problematic conclusions
follow. Hence,
The Father and the Son, together God
and servant, origin and consequence, begetting and begotten, majestic and
humble, are never apart from one another, and the dynamics of their
interrelationship, free, loving and mutual are fulfilled, perfected and brought
to completion by the work of the Holy Spirit.60
We
have already seen that one cannot speak of the Holy Spirit fulfilling,
perfecting and bringing to completion the love of the Father and Son since all
three persons of the Trinity are fully God and thus fully perfect in their
perichoretic mutual love and freedom within the eternal Trinity. What is
perfected by the Spirit is the work of the Trinity within the economy of
salvation.
Missing
from this thinking is any realistic attempt to distinguish without separating
the immanent and economic Trinity. Hence, one then might say that in John’s
Gospel
A unity of Being and purpose between
the Father and the Son is affirmed alongside the Father’s bestowal and the
Son’s consistent deference: “the Father sends Jesus; Jesus obeys and depends on
the Father; he comes from and returns to the Father; and the Father does his
work and speaks his words through him”.61
Further,
the ‘Father communicates self-existence, ultimate right of rule and
determination to the Son (through the Spirit)’.62
But this thinking approximates only too closely the notion of causality
Torrance rightly rejects when he opposes any idea that the Father causes the
deity of the Son and Spirit. What is present here is the very unfortunate
insinuation that God’s love is in need of perfection and that this is what
occurs as Christ lived out his being in the servant form of his activity for
our sakes. Beyond this, after some exegesis of John’s Gospel arguing that the
Father ‘has original self-existence, life and ultimate authority in and from
himself (5.26)’ and that the Father ‘has conferred . . . similar life and
authority to the Son’63 there is a
rather unfortunate but consistent confusion of the processions with the
missions. Finally, we are told that ‘According to Person, ontological priority
and absolute authority belong to the Father. According to Being, ontological
supremacy and absolute reign, rule and authority belong equally to the Father,
the Son and the Holy Spirit.’64 While
this may appear to be an ideal solution on the surface, there is a deep problem
embedded in this suggestion. According to Torrance, any idea that the
principium of the Father with respect to the order of the Trinitarian Persons
might imply ‘an ontological priority, or some prius aut posterius in God’ must
lead to some sort of subordinationism.65
Any denial that all three Persons are equal in authority and power is in
reality a denial of their oneness in being.66
Such
denial inevitably follows the confusion of the immanent and economic Trinity as
when it is said that ‘The Father’s authority has been unilaterally delegated to
the Son’67 and that ‘it is the Father
who has original self-existence, life and ultimate authority in and from
himself’.68 Torrance’s understanding
of this matter is much clearer and to be preferred as when he writes This
priority in order or Monarchy of the Father within the trinitarian relations is
consonant with the Father’s relation to the Son and the Spirit within the
indivisibility of the Triune Being of God. Hence the priority or Monarchy of
the Father within the Holy Trinity must not be taken to imply a priority or
superiority in Deity.69 This is
because ‘It refers to the fact that “the Son is begotten of the Father, not the
Father of the Son”, which is the order manifested in the incarnation between
the Father and his only begotten Son, and is reflected in the sending of the
Holy Spirit by the Father in the name of the Son’.70
Ultimately, the problem here can be skilfully summed up in the words of
Torrance himself:
the inner trinitarian order is not to
be understood in an ontologically differential way, for it does not apply to
the Being or the Deity of the divine Persons which each individually and all
together have absolutely in common, but only to the mysterious “disposition or
economy” which they have among themselves within the unity of the Godhead,
distinguished by position and not status, by form and not being, by sequence
and not power, for they are fully and perfectly equal.71
Torrance
is criticized for allowing the Father’s person to recede ‘ into the background’
because he refuses to think ‘ of the Father’s Person as in himself the
hypostatic root of God’s self-existence, kingly reign and rule’.72 But that was precisely Torrance’s point in
emphasizing the homoousion in the first place and appealing to Athanasius and
others to exclude any notion of a derived deity which is clearly implied
whenever the Father is portrayed as the ‘hypostatic root of God’s
self-existence’. Here it must be said that any attempt to build upon and then
expand Torrance’s thinking by introducing some type of causality into the
eternal Trinity by ascribing eternal obedience to the Son as a condition of his
actions ad extra will always end up in conflict with Torrance’s most important
positive contributions to the doctrine of the Trinity. As we have just seen,
Torrance refuses to confuse the order of the persons with their oneness in
being and thus does indeed avoid modalism, tritheism and subordinationism at
every turn.
1. For a historical discussion see A.
Edward Siecienski, The Filioque: History of a Doctrinal Controversy (New York:
Oxford University Press, 2010). For an intriguing discussion of Barth and
Torrance on the filioque which offers a critical and constructive analysis of
both theologians’ key insights and then attempts to move beyond them in ways
that merit further reflection and discussion but that will not be discussed
here, see Myk Habets, ‘Filioque? Nein: A Proposal for Coherent Coinherence’, in
Trinitarian Theology After Barth (eds Myk Habets and Phillip Tolliday; Eugene,
OR: Wipf and Stock, 2011), pp. 161–202.
2. Yves Congar, I Believe in the Holy
Spirit: vol. III (trans. David Smith; New York: Crossroad, 1997), p. 205,
asserts quite bluntly that ‘The one-sided introduction of the Filioque, without
consulting the Eastern Church, into a creed of ecumenical value was not only a
way of behaving that was canonically illicit, but also an action which devalued
the unity of the Christian family’. T. F. Torrance asserts that the ‘ex Patre
filioque clause ’ was ‘inserted unecumenically into the Creed’ and thus created
‘ a serious impasse in the relations between East and West’, The Christian
Doctrine of God, One Being Three Persons (Edinburgh: T&T Clark, 1996),
p. 186. See also Siecienski, The Filioque, p. 204 and p. 207.
3. Karl Barth, Church Dogmatics, I.1, The
Doctrine of the Word of God (eds G. W. Bromiley and T. F. Torrance; trans. G.
W. Bromiley; 4 vols in 13 pts; Edinburgh: T&T Clark, 1975), p. 479. What
Torrance and Barth both wanted to affirm at all costs was that what God is
towards us in the economy, he is eternally in himself and what he is eternally
in himself he is in the economy. And so both theologians would oppose any
attempt by Eastern theologians to claim that the procession of the Spirit from
the Father took place in God in one way and historically in the mission of the
Spirit from the Son in another. That would indeed drive a wedge between who God
is eternally and who he is in the economy and would have to raise the question
that Torrance himself raises: if the Spirit proceeds only from the Father
eternally but is sent by the Son in history since what the Father does he does
‘through the Son, as Basil pointed out ’ then ‘Does this mean that the sending
of the Spirit by the Son has to do only with revelation and faith, and is not
grounded immanently in the eternal Being of God? If so, would that not call in
question the full homoousial relation of the Holy Spirit to God the Father?’
Torrance, Christian Doctrine of God, p. 187. Torrance clearly thinks it would
and believes Athanasius attacked this very thinking. This would be the
‘incipient subordinationism’ that Torrance finds in the Cappadocians and also
in aspects of Western theology.
4. Thomas F. Torrance, Karl Barth:
Biblical and Evangelical Theologian (Edinburgh: T&T Clark, 1990), p.
131.
5. Thomas F. Torrance, Trinitarian
Perspectives: Toward Doctrinal Agreement (Edinburgh: T&T Clark, 1994),
p. 20.
6. Avery Dulles, S. J., ‘The Filioque: What is at
Stake?’, Concordia Theological Quarterly 59 (January–April 1995), pp. 31–48
(32). See also Congar, Holy Spirit, pp. 52–3.
7. Dulles, ‘The Filioque’, p. 40 and pp.
44–5. Dulles concludes his article saying ‘The toleration of different wording in
the Eastern and Western churches seems, then, in this writer’s judgement,
ecumenically appropriate at the present time’. This approach is based on
suggestions made by Walter Kasper, The God of Jesus Christ (trans. Matthew J.
O’Connell; New York: Crossroad, 1986), pp. 221–2.
8. Congar, Holy Spirit, p. 204.
9. Ibid., p. 206.
10. Ibid.
11. Ibid.
12. See Torrance’s
13. Torrance, Christian Doctrine of God, p.
190.
14. Ibid.
15. Torrance, Trinitarian Perspectives, p.
89.
16. Torrance, Karl Barth, p. 131. Torrance
astutely notes two critical points. First, while the term Father refers
absolutely to the one being of God which the Father has in common with the Son
and Spirit, it also refers relatively to the Father in relation to the Son,
that is, to the Person of the Father. Second, Torrance believes that the
Cappadocians conflated these two senses by conceiving the unity of God ‘ as
deriving “from the Person of the Father” and in that way they replaced the
Nicene formula which held that the unity of God derived “from the Being of the
Father . . .”’ In Torrance’s view this meant that ‘ procession is regarded as
taking place between different modes of existence or relations of origin, which
is hardly satisfactory for it falls short of affirming the homoousion of the Spirit’,
Christian Doctrine of God, p. 186. Gregory Nazianzen was the exception here,
ibid., pp. 186–7. Nonetheless the Cappadocians rejected Arian and Macedonian
ideas that the Spirit was created by God. Augustine also rejected the Arian
idea that the Son is subordinate to the Father by affirming the filioque.
However, Western theologians following this view mistakenly also espoused the
idea that the Spirit proceeds ‘ from the Father principally (principaliter)’
and so the conflation seen in the Cappadocian view also seeped into the
theology of the West.
17. Ibid., p. 132,208.
18. Ibid., p. 132. Like Torrance, Barth
believed that materially East and West did not disagree about the procession of
the Spirit from the beginning (Barth, CD I.1, p. 477).
19. Ibid., p. 209.
20. Thomas F. Torrance, The Trinitarian
Faith: The Evangelical Theology of the Ancient Catholic Church (Edinburgh:
T&T Clark, 1988), p. 237.
21. Ibid.
22. Ibid., p. 238.
23. Gregory/Basil, Ep. 38.4 cited in
Torrance, Trinitarian Faith, p. 238.
24. Torrance, Trinitarian Faith, p. 238,
with references to Gregory Nazianzen to support his critique and to support his
own view, following Gregory Nazianzen, that the Godhead can be referred to as
the Μοναρχία.
25. Ibid., p. 238.
26. Ibid., pp. 238–9.
27. Ibid., p. 239.
28. Ibid.
29. Ibid.
30. Ibid., p. 240.
31. Ibid.
32. Ibid.
33. Ibid.
34. Ibid.
35. Ibid., pp. 240–1.
36. Ibid., p. 241.
37. Ibid.
38. Ibid.
39. Ibid.
40. Ibid., p. 242.
41. At this point Barth connects this
thinking with his rejection of ebionite and docetic approaches to Jesus, just
as Torrance does in following Barth in this.
42. At least one contemporary theologian
observes that Barth ‘ distinguishes between two forms of subordination within
the Trinity’. First, ‘“Subordination [Unterordnungsverhältnis] regarding their
deity”’ (I.1, p. 393) which Barth unequivocally rejects, and second ‘“the
relation of subordination [Unterordnungsverhältnis]”’ (I.1, p. 413) which Barth
favours as ‘ a matter of the distinction and relationality between the various
modes of being of the one essence’, Adam J. Johnson, God’s Being in
Reconciliation: The Theological Basis of the Unity and Diversity of the
Atonement in the Theology of Karl Barth (London/New York: T&T Clark
International, 2012), pp. 73–4, n. 37. Johnson concludes by saying that ‘Barth
reaffirms and more fully explores the nature of this Trinitarian subordination
in CD IV.1, pp. 200–10’, ibid., p. 74.
43. Torrance, Christian Doctrine of God, p.
180. Importantly, Torrance claims that this is part of the significance of 1
Cor. 15.24 and Phil. 2.7–10.
44. Ibid.
45. Ibid. 46
46. See, for example, Paul Dafydd Jones,
‘Obedience, Trinity, and Election: Thinking With and Beyond the Church Dogmatics’,
in Trinity and Election in Contemporary Theology (ed. Dempsey; Grand Rapids:
Eerdmans, 2011), pp. 138–61. He claims ‘ that the eternal identity of the Son
encompasses and, in a sense, is constituted by the concrete life of Jesus
Christ’, p. 155. And he also argues that ‘the incarnation, as an elective event
of divine self-transformation, intensifies God’s triune self-differentiation’,
Paul Daffyd Jones, The Humanity of Christ: Christology in Karl Barth’s Church
Dogmatics (London and New York: T&T Clark, 2008), p. 212. Both of these
ideas undermine the unity and Trinity within the immanent Trinity by making the
eternal Son’s deity in some sense dependent on events that will occur or do
occur ad extra. Jesus’ human life does not constitute his identity as the
eternal Son and election does not transform the Son since he remains the God he
always was and is even in the incarnation. For a rather overt example of
someone espousing the idea of a dependent deity, see Wolfhart Pannenberg: ‘God,
through the creation of the world, made himself radically dependent on this
creation and on its history’ (italics in original), ‘Problems of a Trinitarian
Doctrine of God’, Dialog 26 (1987), p. 255. See also Ted Peters, GOD as
Trinity: Relationality and Temporality in Divine Life (Louisville, KY:
Westminster/John Knox Press, 1993), who claims that ‘God is in the process of
becoming Godself through relationship with the temporal creation’, p. 92, and
says that ‘the fullness of God as Trinity is a reality yet to be achieved in
the eschatological consummation’, p. 16. Finally, he properly claims that ‘the
God of Jesus Christ is inextricably and passionately involved in the affairs of
human history’ and then mistakenly concludes that ‘this involvement is
constitutive of the trinitarian life proper’, p. 82.
47. See, for example, Paul D. Molnar,
Incarnation and Resurrection: Toward a Contemporary Understanding (Grand
Rapids: Eerdmans, 2007), pp. 244–60, esp. p. 255.
48. See IV.1, p. 157, pp. 211–83 and Thomas
F. Torrance, Atonement: The Person and Work of Christ (ed. Robert T. Walker;
Milton Keynes, UK: Paternoster and Downers Grove: IVP, 2009), p. 148, 184.
49. See, for example, Torrance, Christian
Doctrine of God, p. 199, The Doctrine of Jesus Christ (Eugene, OR: Wipf and
Stock, 2002), pp. 146–7 and p. 163; Barth, IV.2, p. 357. Both theologians agree
that ‘it is God, really God in Christ, who suffers and bears the sin of the
world – that is the particle of truth ... as Karl Barth once said, in the
Patripassian heresy’ (The Doctrine of Jesus Christ, p. 167).
50. In the rare instance where Torrance
speaks of ‘ a “before” and an “after” in the life of God’ he attempts to make
sense of the fact that the incarnation was something new even for God. See
Thomas F. Torrance, Preaching Christ Today: The Gospel and Scientific Thinking
(Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1994), p. 69 and Paul D. Molnar, Thomas F. Torrance:
Theologian of the Trinity (Farnham: Ashgate, 2009), pp. 253–9. See also
Christian Doctrine of God, pp. 241–2.
51. Torrance, Trinitarian Perspectives, p.
66; cf. also ibid., pp. 28–36, pp. 118–20 and p. 133.
52. Ibid., p. 67.
53. For a full treatment of this matter,
see Paul D. Molnar, ‘The Obedience of the Son in the Theology of Karl Barth and
of Thomas F. Torrance’, Scottish Journal of Theology 67 (2014), pp. 50–69.
54. Compare this to Torrance’s assertion
that God’s eternal being is ‘ also a divine Becoming’ but that ‘This does not
mean that God ever becomes other than he eternally is or that he passes over
from becoming into being something else.... His Becoming is not a becoming on
the way toward being or toward a fullness of being . . . Becoming expresses the
dynamic nature of his Being’, Christian Doctrine of God, p. 242.
55. Torrance, Christian Doctrine of God, p.
144.
56. George Hunsinger, ‘Election and the
Trinity: Twenty-Five Theses on the Theology of Karl Barth’, Modern Theology 24
(April 2008), pp. 181–3 explains perfectly that when Barth says that Jesus
Christ is the subject of election he is not speaking without qualification.
57. While I think much of Rowan Williams’
critique of Barth is off the mark, his observation about this remark is
interesting: ‘What, if anything, this can possibly mean, neither Barth nor his
interpreters have succeded (sic) in telling us’, ‘Barth on the Triune God’, in
Karl Barth: Studies of his Theological Method (ed. S. W. Sykes; Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1979), p. 175. Here Barth was inconsistent in distinguishing
without separating the processions and missions, the immanent and economic
Trinity.
58. See II.1, p. 306. and I.1, p. 427 as
well as IV.1, p. 113 and especially IV.2, p. 755 where Barth says ‘God loves,
and to do so He does not need any being distinct from His own as the object of
His love. If He loves the world and us, this is a free overflowing of the love
in which He is and is God and with which he is not content, although He might
be, since neither the world nor ourselves are indispensable to His love and
therefore to His being’. Torrance agrees with this (Christian Doctrine of God,
p.242).
59. Benjamin Dean, ‘Person and Being:
Conversation with T. F. Torrance about the Monarchy of God’, International
Journal of Systematic Theology 15 (January 2013), pp. 58–77 (69).
60. Ibid.
61. Ibid., p. 71.
62. Ibid.
63. Ibid.
64. Ibid., p. 72.
65. Torrance, Trinitarian Perspectives, p.
66.
66. See Torrance, Christian Doctrine of
God, p. 176.
67. Dean, ‘Person and Being’, p. 71.
68. Ibid.
69. Torrance, Christian Doctrine of God, p.
176.
70. Ibid.
71. Ibid.
72. Dean, ‘Person and Being’, p. 74.
Bibliography
Molnar, Paul, “Ecumenical Perspectives on the Filioque for the 21st Century (Article), 2014,” pp. 3-37
No comments:
Post a Comment