Introduction
There
have been approximately 45 million medical/surgical abortions performed in the
United States since the legalization of abortion in 1973 by Roe v. Wade. This is not including the abortions
that occur through abortifacient contraception, which some have estimated to be
around 2.8 million abortions per year
in the United States alone. The
statistical evidence clearly demonstrates that our culture does not appreciate the
value of human life. However,
as Catholics, we are called to defend the dignity of human life from the very
moment of conception. As the Catechism of
the Catholic Church states, “human
life must be respected and protected absolutely from the moment of conception.
From the first moment of his existence, a human being must be recognized as having
the rights of a person – among which is the inviolable right of every innocent
being to life.” If we are to combat the culture of
death, we must present a coherent account of
the human person which ensures the full personal status of early stage human
embryos. To accomplish this task, I will be using the Aristotelian-Thomistic
hylomorphic framework, which distinguishes material substances according to
form and matter. Furthermore, I will be defending the position that
hylomorphism is completely compatible with immediate hominization, utilizing
Rev. Nicanor Austriaco’s systems hylomorphism which attempts to synthesize
systems biology with the hylomorphic theory. Finally, I will be arguing that the rational soul is the integrating
principle of the human body, and that we are endowed with souls at the moment
of conception.
Demonstrating the personal
status of human embryos is paramount
Abortion
advocates, although willing to admit the humanity
of early stage human embryos, reject their moral status. Australian philosopher
Peter Singer is a prime example of this,
To describe a being as 'human'
is to use a term that straddles two distinct notions: membership of the species
Homo sapiens, and being a person, in the sense of a rational or
self-conscious being. If 'human' is taken as equivalent to 'person', the second
premise of the argument, which asserts that the foetus is a human being, is
clearly false; for one cannot plausibly argue that a foetus is either rational
or self-conscious. If, on the other hand, 'human' is taken to mean no more than
'member of the species Homo sapiens', then it needs to be shown why mere
membership of a given biological species should be a sufficient basis for a
right to life. Rather, the defender of abortion may wish to argue, we should
look at the foetus for what it is - the actual characteristics it possesses -
and value its life accordingly.
Singer distinguishes three forms of consciousness:
(1) pre-consciousness, (2) consciousness, and (3) self-consciousness. Only
those who are self-conscious have an absolute right to life. In other words,
the pre-born, infants, and the mentally handicapped don’t necessarily have the
right to life. Singer seems to adopt a materialistic account of the universe, which
reduces everything to physical matter. To refute materialism we need to establish
two things: (1) that human beings are a composite of matter and form,
and (2) that the rational soul is immaterial.
Presenting the hylomorphic account of the human person.
The term Hylomorphism is
a composite of two Greek words “hyle” (matter) and “morphe” (form). Matter, for
Aquinas, does not refer to physical substances but a “material thing’s potentiality
for substantial change. It is not, he thinks, a substance… He takes this to be nothing but the potential
that a material thing has for undergoing substantial change. He does not think
that it is something having a form.” When
the Scholastics used the term form
they were not referring to the shape of a material object, rather they meant
that which makes something the kind of thing that it is. Man by definition is a
rational animal, so the form of man
is a rational soul. To quote the Council of Vienne (1312): “We reject as erroneous
and contrary to the truth of the Catholic faith every doctrine or proposition
rashly asserting that the substance of the rational or intellectual soul is not
of itself and essentially the form of the human body…”
Matter
and form are two principles of a substance or being, but they never exist
separately. So it is wrong to think of a human being as “composed” of a body
and soul as though these were two physically distinct things. We cannot divide
the visible human and say this part is the body and this part is the soul
(except perhaps a disembodied soul).
Demonstrating the
immateriality of the soul is essential
Those
who reject the inherent dignity of human embryos typically operate within a
materialistic framework. Since materialists reject immaterial realities, they
unsurprisingly also reject the existence of immaterial souls. If we are to make
a case for the dignity of human embryos, we need to demonstrate the
immateriality of the soul.
The soul is
immaterial
We can demonstrate the immateriality of the soul in
several ways. First we can note the existence of immaterial realities in
general such as abstract concepts, categories
of logic, numbers, etc. Various philosophers have attempted to reconcile
empiricism (the notion that all knowledge is derived from sense-experience)
with idealism (e.g., George Berkley and Immanuel Kant). The problem with
empiricism is that we can't prove by sense experience that all of reality is
just sense data or mental phenomena or ideals. Using the example of thoughts,
we cannot perceive our thoughts through the senses.
Secondly, our ability to abstract universals from particulars requires a principle that
can extract immaterial realities from corporeal entities (such as a triangle
and triangleness). This can only be done by an immaterial principle that we
call the rational soul. Thirdly, we can note the universal human desire for the
“infinite and absolute truth which is God.”
This universal desire points to a transcendent quality about the soul. It suggests
that the rational soul is ordered towards the greatest good, namely, God
Himself. To quote,
The
human will is never satisfied with what it possesses, but desires goods that
are always greater and can be content only in the possession of the infinite
and absolute Good which is God. Therefore we find in the human soul a capacity
for the infinite which no partial truth and no limited good can satisfy. A
being, however, is happy only when its desires are satisfied. Since the soul
can be satisfied only by infinite Truth and absolute Good, one must conclude
that there is in the soul a desire for perfect and absolute happiness, that is,
for that happiness which only perfect Truth and absolute Good can give it.
When do we receive
the rational soul?
According
to biologist Rev. Nicanor Austriaco O.P., “For both the Peripatetic Philosopher
[Aristotle] and the Angelic Doctor [Thomas Aquinas], a human rational soul
cannot inform a body unless that body possesses a level of complexity and
organization appropriate to that form of life. This is the theory of delayed
hominization.” St. Thomas, following the opinion of
Aristotle,
thought that “ensoulment” occurred forty days after fertilization for boys, and
ninety days for girls. In addition to adopting Aristotle’s
view of delayed animation, Aquinas also followed his view that the human embryo
underwent a succession of souls: first a vegetative (or nutritive) soul, then
an animal (or sensitive) soul, and then, finally, a human (or rational) soul.
He believed that the semen of the father was the “agent cause of material
developments in utero. It was
responsible for setting in motion the precise sequence of changes involved in
the development of menstrual matter into a material subject appropriate for a
rational soul.”
Rev. Nicanor Austriaco adds, “This was a crucial element of a
classical theory of delayed hominization. Today, we know that the semen does
not even survive the first five days of embryonic development. However, without
the semen, what organizes the embryonic body? What prepares the embryo to
receive the rational soul?”
We must receive the
rational soul at the moment of conception
Austriaco’s
question leaves the classical hylomorphic account in serious trouble. Instead
of postulating that
human development is a discontinuous
process involving the sequential appearance of three separate and distinct
substances… systems hylomorphism with its species-based understanding of souls
is able to acknowledge the temporal unity of the developing organism—the
developing human being is one throughout development because it has one human
soul—while retaining the basic framework of hylomorphism.
According to systems biology, “the
human organism as a dynamic, complex, and seamlessly integrated network not of
organs or cells but of molecules, including DNA, RNA, lipids,
metabolites, and proteins, connected by reaction pathways which generate shape,
mass, energy, and information transfer over the course of a human lifetime.”
Rev. Nicanor Austriaco defines systems biology as,
In contrast to the prevailing
reductionist and mechanistic view, the organism is seen here as a single,
unified whole, a complex and dynamic net work of interacting molecules that
appear and then disappear in time… From the systems perspective, this
particular pattern, this organization of the molecules of the human being,
would be a manifestation of his immaterial soul. As noted above, one
metaphysical principle that governs the relationship between the body and its
soul is that matter has to be properly disposed to receive a form. From within
the context of the systems perspective, this principle means that matter is disposed
to receive a soul when it contains all the molecules required to give rise to
the species-specific network that corresponds to a particular type of soul.
Thus, a human body is disposed to receive a human soul at fertilization and
would cease being disposed when the molecular network disintegrates.
One of the questions of modern
philosophy is how an organism retains its identity over the course of
substantial physical change. If it is true, as some scientists suggest, that
“98% of the atoms of the adult human
body, including those found in the brain and nervous system, are replaced in
about two years,”
then how can we legitimately claim that the organism is essentially the same
over the course of time? This is only possible within the hylomorphic framework
which distinguishes between substantial and accidental forms. As
Rev. Austriaco notes, “[The
systems-hylomorphic account] explains the stable dynamism of the human being. A
man is stable because of his substantial form, yet he is dynamic because he is
capable of changing his accidental forms… During accidental changes, the
substantial form or soul remains, ensuring the integrity and identity of the
organism.”
He continues,
“It is the soul that makes a man a human being by organizing the matter,
determining his identity and stability, and specifying his biological end.”
Conclusion
In
this article I have demonstrated several things: (1) that organisms are a
composite of form and matter, (2) that human beings have an immaterial soul,
(3) that the rational soul is the integrating principle of the human body, and
(4) that we must necessarily be endowed with souls at the moment of conception.
Based on this metaphysical account of the human person, abortion constitutes
homicide properly speaking. Yet if this is the case, then our laws should
reflect this reality. In fact the 14th Amendment of
the Constitution, as well as the Declaration of Independence, already grants
‘persons’ the right to life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness. Since
governments exist to ensure the well-being of its citizen, then we should enact
laws protecting the most vulnerable. I would even argue that governments should
not only illegalize abortion, but criminalize it as well.
Bibliography
Thomas. (1912). The Summa theologica of St. Thomas Aquinas. London: Burns
Oates & Washbourne.
Austriaco, N. (2004) “Immediate Hominization from the Systems
Perspective.” The National Catholic Bioethics Quarterly, Volume 4, Issue 4:
719-338.
Austriaco, N. (2003) “Is the brain-dead patient really dead?”
Studia Moralia.41: 277-308.
Austriaco, N. (2003) “The Pre-Implantation Embryo Revisited: A
Two-Celled Individual or Two Individual Cells?” The Linacre Quarterly, Volume
70, Number 2, Article 4.
The Hylomorphic Structure of Thomisitic Moral Theology from
the Perspective of a Systems Biology (Nicanor Austriaco)
A Hylomorphic Account of Personal Identity (Jeremy Skrzypek)
Dynamic Structure or Enduring Activity? Thomas Aquinas and
Contemporary Neo-Aristotelians on Substantial Form (Jeremy Skrzypek)
Is the Early Stage Embryo a Person? (W. Jerome Bracken)
Is the Human Embryo a Person? (Kevin D. O’Rourke)
Abortion: The myths, the realities, and the argument (Germain
Grisez)
When Do People Begin? (Germain Grisez)
St Thomas Aquinas and Abortion (William Newton)
Protecting Prenatal Persons: Does the Fourteenth Amendment
Prohibit Abortion (Joshua Craddock)
Personhood status of the human zygote, embryo, fetus (John
Janez Miklavcic & Paul Flaman)
Rational Souls and the Beginning of Life: A Reply to Robert
Pasnau (John Haldane and Patrick Lee)
The Roman Catholic Church and Abortion: An Historical
Perspective (Donald DeMarco)
Mind you the same author you cite for
delayed animation (i.e., St. Thomas), considered abortion a mortal sin
pre-ensolutement.
Nicanor Austriaco, “Is the brain-dead patient really dead?” (Studia Moralia 41, 2003), 304.